公 法 评 论 你们必晓得真理,真理必叫你们得以自由。
The Significance of Federalism in Redesigning
Constitutional Systems
Daniel J. Elazar
转自宪政文本
Federalism has had multiple significances for designing and redesigning
constitutional systems. In the first place, modern constitutionalism developed
out of federal-covenantal principles as they developed through a synthesis of
theological and political ideas during the Protestant Reformation and were
transplanted to the New World of British North America in the seventeenth
century. In the second place, there is the special character of federal
constitutional systems which, in their most proper expression, combine two or
at times three sets of constitutions -- for federal, state, and at times local
governments. These sets of constitutions must be basically complementary but
also raise problems of conflicts between them that must be dealt with
constitutionally. Third, federal systems have been especially important in
contributing to the problems of modern constitutional design, especially
popular participation in constitutional design. Finally, the spread of
federalistic constitutional design for a variety of systems, especially in the
interstate arena, has become a post-modern phenomenon worthy of special
consideration because of its special characteristics and newness. All four of
these topics are treated in this paper.
The Three Dimensions of the Constitution
Aristotle, the founder of political science, identified three
dimensions of every constitution. The one most familiar to us is the frame of
government which defines the powers, structures and functions of the government
of a particular polity. The second may determine the socio-economic dimension
of the constitution, that is to say, the distribution of power within the
political society served by the frame of government that gives the frame its
reality as a power-map. The third dimension is the moral constitution, that is
to say, the normative basis of the constitutional system including the rules of
the political game acceptable in the polity. Every constitutional system has
all three dimensions for which Aristotle used the term
"constitution." We would today use the term "political
system." Nevertheless, it is good to remind ourselves of the Aristotelian
usage because this three-fold model provides the constitutional basis of the
political system.
We may go further in our constitutional examination to identify three
great periods of constitutional concern in the Western world: ancient, medieval
and modern. While constitutions of every period require all three dimensions,
we can identify the emphasis on one dimension or another in each of the three. In
ancient times, constitutions tended to emphasize the socio-economic dimension
as the basis of constitutionalism. This can be seen in the way both Greek and
biblical constitutions emphasized rules of family and inheritance, the
organization of the land system which provided the economic basis for most
polities, the religious foundations of the polity, and commercial and social
relations among families within it.
Medieval constitutionalism, on the other hand, emphasized the moral
dimension. That is to say, it did very little in the way of specifying frames
of government or the distribution of power in society, but emphasized the moral
rules by which people were expected to live without providing for their
effective enforcement. Consequently, medieval constitutionalism, which often
looks so excellent in its aspirations, essentially failed in its applications.
In part to correct the problems of medieval constitutionalism, modern
constitutionalism emphasized the third dimension, frames of government, that is
to say, the specification of the way power and authority should be structured,
distributed, and limited, checked or balanced and what functions government
should perform. The modern frame of government emphasis has been such as to
often exclude recognition or proper consideration of the other two dimensions
but all of the dimensions are equally important for constitutional systems.
The Three Sources of Polity: Hierarchical, Organic and Covenantal
In the very first Federalist paper, Publius (in this case Alexander
Hamilton) states in the very first paragraph:
"It has been frequently remarked, that it seems to have been
reserved to the people of this country, by their conduct and example, to decide
the important question, whether societies of men are really capable or not, of
establishing good government from reflection and choice, or whether they are
forever destined to depend, for their political constitutions, on accident and
force."
This question, indeed, was a fundamental one for the entire federal
constitutional ratification process as seen by the Americans in 1787. Beyond
that, it reflects and points us toward the significant truth that in all of
political theory and political science only three basic sources and forms of
polity have been identified: the hierarchical form, originally established by
conquest and force; the organic form, that has emerged incrementally or through
what Publius calls "accident"; and the covenantal form, established
by pacts among equals arrived at through reflection and choice. There may be
various combinations of these three sources in the case of any participation of
polity but the critical one is ultimately distinguishable in each case.
Conquest can be understood to include not only its most direct
manifestation, a conqueror gaining control of a land or a people, but also such
subsidiary ways as a revolutionary conquest of an existing state, a coup
d'etat, or even an entrepreneur conquering market and organizing his control
through corporate means. Conquest tends to produce hierarchically organized
regimes ruled in an authoritarian manner; power pyramids with the conqueror on
top, his agents in the middle, and the people underneath the entire structure. The
original expression of this kind of polity was the Pharaonic state of ancient
Egypt. It was hardly an accidental those rulers who brought the Pharaonic state
to its fullest development had the pyramids built as their tombs. Although the
Pharaonic model has been judged illegitimate in western society, modern
totalitarian theories, particularly fascism and nazism, represent an attempt to
give it a certain theoretical legitimacy.
Organic evolution involves the development of political life from its
beginnings in families, tribes, and villages to large polities in such a way
that institutions, constitutional relationships, and power alignments emerge in
response to the interaction between past precedent and changing circumstances,
with a minimum of deliberate constitutional choice. The end result tends to be
a polity with a single center of power organized in one of several ways. Classic
Greek political thought emphasized the organic evolution of the polity and
rejected any other means of polity-building as deficient or improper. The
organic model is closely related to the concept of natural law in the political
order.
The organic model has proved most attractive to political philosophers
precisely because at its best, it seems to reflect the natural order of things.
Thus it has received the most intellectual and academic attention. However,
just as conquest tends to produce hierarchically organized regimes ruled in an
authoritarian manner, organic evolution tends to produce oligarchic regimes
which, at their best, have an aristocratic flavor, and at their worst are
simply the rule of the many by the few. In the first, the goal is to control
the center of power.
Covenantal foundings emphasize the deliberate coming together of humans
as equals to establish bodies politic in such a way that all reaffirm their
fundamental equality and retain their basic rights. Even the Hobbesian covenant
-- and Hobbes specifically uses that term -- which establishes a polity in
which power is vested in a single sovereign, maintains this fundamental
equality although, in practice, it would not be able to coexist with the system
of rule that Hobbes proposes. Polities whose origins are covenantal reflect the
exercise of constitutional choice and broad-based participation in
constitutional design. Polities founded by covenant are essentially federal in
character, in the original meaning of the term -- whether they are federal in
structure or not. That is to say, each polity is a matrix compounded of equal
confederates who come together freely and retain their respective integrities
are republican by definition and power within them must be diffused among many
centers or the various cells within the matrix.
The Impact of Covenantalism on Modern Constitutionalism
The Protestant Reformation, especially through Reformed Protestantism,
which later became known, somewhat mistakenly, as Calvinism, challenged the
fundamentals of medieval order, including medieval constitutionalism, on both
theological and political grounds. In challenging the Catholic Church, the
Reformed Protestants essentially challenged the entire medieval political
theological order, attacking political tyranny as well as religious hierarchy,
since medieval Christendom was based upon hierarchy through and through (even
feudalism was only a device that modified the pyramid by establishing
constitutional rules for its decentralization to descending levels of elites). This
was done through the federal theology (their term) which they developed to
explain the partnership arrangement between Gold and man upon what, for they,
the world rested. It was for this purpose that they invented the term
"federal theology" and applied it to politics as well. This was the
first time the term "Federal" was used for such purposes.
To be effective, this challenge had to be one not only of
manifestations but of foundations as well. In general, Protestant reformers
turned back to the Bible. Presumably, the Bible was the ultimate foundation of
the medieval order as well but one which the reformers emphasized that the
Church had perverted and distorted.
The Reformed Protestant leaders who studied the Bible discovered in it
the covenantal premises and expressions that assaulted the very foundations of
the hierarchical order and denied hierarchy the divine legitimacy which all of
Christendom believed to be necessary for any political order. By the medieval
theo-political order, it delegitimized the tyranny of hierarchies. Moreover, as
practical men, the Reformed Protestant leaders reconstructed the bodies politic
which they inherited or established to reflect their understanding of the
biblical covenantal system. Their constitutions of government were still
rudimentary but their efforts at reconstitution or founding were rooted in
pacts -- covenants between rulers and ruled, magistrates and citizens -- within
the congregation of believers, thereby placing them all on an essentially equal
footing.
It soon became apparent that covenants, while necessary for foundations
of the new political order, were not sufficient. Constitutions of government
were needed to translate those covenants into real institutions that would be
both effective and be true to the principles of the covenants that underlay
them. Those rules became the basis of modern constitutionalism.
In continental Europe modern constitutionalism emerged in those
borderlands stretching from northern Italy to the North Sea, the area once
embraced by the Middle Frankish kingdom established for Lothar, the oldest son
of Charlemagne, at the end of the ninth century, a territory that embraced what
later became both the heartland and most of the peripheries of Reformed
Protestant ascendancy in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries. Consitutionalism
was even more powerful in its emergence in British North America, most
particularly in New England in the seventeenth century. Indeed, the effective
chain of modern constitutionalism can be traced back to the constitutional
documents of the Plymouth Colony, the Massachusetts Colony, Connecticut, and
Rhode Island of the 1630s and 1640s, and from those early experiments on
through the adoption of the Constitution of the United States of America in
1787-1789.
Developments proceeded along two fronts: First cam the elaboration and
sophistication of systems of constitutional rules embodied in the documents
and, then, the secularization of those constitutional documents. The first New
England constitutions were either lists of principles without extensive
procedures or elaborate codes, often included by adoption, from the Bible. Over
time, these developed into better designed constitutional documents providing
the institutional frameworks and increasingly the rights protections required
in modern constitutions. Indeed, one can say that with the framing of the
American state constitutions during the Revolutionary War modern
constitutionalism had arrived and reached its apotheosis in the federal
constitution of 1787.
This tradition was adopted with a few variants by the French
revolutionaries after 1789, by the Polish revolutionaries in 1792, and from
then became the standard for constitutional development in the modern world. The
next great spate of constitution-making was in Latin America in the early
nineteenth century following the federal and constitutional forms of the United
States. Latin Americans endowed their constitutions with a new meaning for
federalism, seeing in federalism not simply an instrumental device for good
government but also the embodiment of liberalism against the hierarchies
established by the Spanish and Portuguese during the colonial period. In many
respects they represented hopes for the future rather than concrete and
currently implementable power maps.
As modern constitutionalism spread, its overt covenantal basis
disappeared. The covenants or their secular versions, political compacts, had
been already entered into -- to establish peoples as to form polities -- and
the constitutions were written to effectuate them in constitutions. once those
constitutions were in place, there was no need to appeal beyond them in most
cases. Constitutionalism came to replace direct covenantalism except under
those conditions of foundings or refoundings where new covenants had to be cut.
This replacement came to be so complete during the course of the
nineteenth century that the covenantal foundations of constitutionalism were
forgotten by all but a handful of scholars. Constitutionalism by itself became
a hallowed as well as a practical means of establishing and maintaining democratic
republicanism, but its federal/covenantal roots should not be forgotten in the
process of seeking how to effectuate and to better constitutional systems.
Federal Constitutional Systems
As modern constitutionalism spread, distinctions between federal and
unitary states and systems also became more pronounced in the constitutional as
well as in other spheres. Unitary systems required only one constitution for
the whole and all of its parts. Indeed, in many cases only the whole was
officially denominated a government, the other units of political organization
within the unitary state were designed "authorities," provinces, or
"countries" (land, pays) in the cultural rather than the political
sense.
In federal systems, on the other hand, the idea was a greater or lesser
measure of coequality among governments within the political system, certainly
federal and state and at times local as well. Each of them was to have its own
constitution, reflecting the will of the people who constituted that particular
government and had to live according to its rules. Thus federal systems rest
upon multiple constitutional documents, each drafted by, for, or on behalf of
the particular public it is designed to serve. All such constitutions must be
considered in order to fully understand the constitutional framework and system
of federal polities.
While each of these constitutions may be independent, the federal
constitution and the constitutions of the constituent units must share certain
common principles and premises, a common spirit if you will, in order to fit
into a common mosaic. Thus, for example, the federal and state constitutions of
the United States are all based upon tripartite separation of powers systems,
while the federal and provincial or state constitutions of Canada and Australia
are all based upon the combination of federal and Westminster parliamentary
systems. Indeed, to the best of this writer's knowledge, none have ever even
raised the possibility of following a different course in a serious manner, not
to mention the harmonization or shared values among the polities within each
system. Indeed, we have seen the consequences of the demise of shared values in
former Yugoslavia or the intensification of those shared values which lead to
conflict rather than cooperation, even if their constitutional expectations and
systems remain much the same.
It is true that some federal systems have only one federal constitution
that includes within it constitutional provisions for state and local
government as well as multi-level intergovernmental collaboration. Nigeria is
an example of this. In almost every case they represent very hierarchical
federal systems that barely meet the definition of federalism if, indeed, they
do. Again, Nigeria is a good example.
Even in those federal systems where separate constitutions for the
major constituent units are not required, to the extent that the systems have
been properly federal, matters have evolved in that direction. Canada may be
the outstanding example of this. The Canadian provinces, following the English
model, did not need to adopt provincial constitutions, but over time basic laws
have developed that have become de facto constitutional documents, although not
entrenched in the normal constitutional manner. They have gained increasing
respect from the provincial parliamentary and other governing authorities.
Often, local constitutional documents are denominated
"charters" or the equivalent, indicating that they are not coequal
with the federal and state constitutions but are derivative from the powers of
one or the other. The semantic distinction is an important one, as the rulings
of constitutional courts dealing with those charters reveal. The struggle
between state constitutions and local charters may seem to be exactly like the
struggle within unitary systems but the addition of a federal government is a
complicating factor since it allows localities to develop a more independent
constitutional tradition by appealing in both directions. The United States,
which probably started with less and has gone further than any other federal
system, may be the best example of this.
In the original American constitutional system no provision was made
for separate local constitutional standing. First of all, the matter was left
to the states and the states usually followed the English example of close
subordination of local authorities to the state government. Over time, however,
the very existence of federalism led to the development of greater local
autonomy through general laws empowering localities, without the need for
individual recourse to the state legislature for every charter matter, and
through home rule provisions that enabled the local governments to adopt their
own constitutions, even if for only limited purposes.
The existence of multiple constitutions from a single constitutional
system places a premium on intergovernmental relations, including
intergovernmental constitutional relations, an especially important dimension
in the significance of federalism on constitutional systems. All polities
beyond the scope of direct rule by one person have intergovernmental relations,
but there is a major difference in the character and quality of
intergovernmental relations in federal and non-federal systems. So, too, there
are qualitative differences between hierarchical, organic, and covenantal
(federal) systems. In the latter, intergovernmental relations must be truly
intergovernmental, although constitutionalism, perhaps because of its
covenantal roots, has introduced a measure of potential autonomy into
intergovernmental relations in all constitutional systems that is worthy of
further investigation in each specific case. For example, the changes that have
taken place in highly centralized and unitary France in the past three decades
deserve to be noted and examined.
Federal Dimensions of Constitutional Design
Just as federal systems are among the major pioneers of modern
constitutions, so, too, have they been pioneers in the development of patterns
of continuing constitutional design. One of the foremost inventions of modern
constitutionalism was the possibility for constitutional revision within the
constitutional system. Prior to that, most constitutional revision had to be
achieved through some kind of revolution since the system itself did not make
adequate provision for change except perhaps through authoritative
interpretation. Changes of the latter normally were limited since it was not
easy to justify them. It took a very daring group of interpreters to make major
changes through constitutional interpretation alone. It was not impossible, but
it was rare, even very rare. Moreover, the authoritative interpreters were
almost always the people in power, which meant that their willingness to make
changes was often limited since the needed changes often went against their
immediate personal interests.
One of the great achievements of modern constitutionalism, part of its
republican and democratic character, was the introduction of provisions for
constitutional revision within the constitutional document itself. These took
two forms: either a formal procedure for constitutional amendment through the
institutions established by the constitution or formal provisions for calling a
special constitutional convention which would look at the whole document or any
part of it for that purpose. Both devices were developed at about the same
time.
The United States and the individual states were pioneers of both
devices at the time of the American Revolution or immediately thereafter. Both
have served federal polities well. Amendment through the formal institutions has
been the most widespread device in the federal arena while both that kind of
amendment and periodic constitutional conventions have been useful devices in
the state arenas. The study of state conventions both for the foundings and
constitutional revisions in the various American states has been a subject of
no little interest, although it needs to be better studied within the larger
political science framework of contemporary political science ideas and
methodology.
Subsequently, a third device was developed, the constitutional
referendum. Switzerland pioneered in this form of constitutional change and it
soon spread to other federal systems, particularly the American states, though
it has not been used with regard to the U.S. constitution. The Swiss have
developed the constitutional referendum to a fine art and in some respects an
exact science. All three arenas of government in Switzerland use constitutional
referenda and their use in connection with the federal constitution involves a
combination of federal and state arrangements since majorities have to be
secured by canton and not only through a federal majority. Referenda are in
such demand that a calendar has been established scheduling them so that not
too many will occur in any one election.
The use of the referendum as a constitutional design device has spread
to some three-fifths of the American states where it is used much more freely
than in Switzerland, although not always in such quantities. California, in
particular, with its very large and politically activist population, has
developed an exaggerated use of the constitutional referendum. California's
people expect to be involved in state and local constitutional design. The
state's various interests are able to organize to take advantage of the
opportunities offered and funding is generally available from them to make that
possible. The popular referendum has become a weapon in the state's normal
process of political conflict. A few years ago when the matter of state
regulation of automobile insurance came before the voters, six different and
often contradictory amendments were on the ballot in the same election, the
purpose of several of which was mostly to confuse the voters rather than to
secure any kind of reasonable change.
California has not adapted the Swiss system of setting a referendum
timetable. Whatever passes the post in terms of the signatures on the
appropriate petitions is placed on the ballot at the very next statewide
election. This has lead to very long and complex ballots with more propositions
than even especially attuned voters can assimilate and, as indicated above,
often contradictory ones designed to obfuscate rather than elucidate.
California is the extreme case. Most other states have been able to
keep the referendum system within balance even without special legislation. In
the United States and Switzerland it is no doubt the most widespread form of
popular involvement in constitutional design for states and localities.
In contrast, efforts to call constitutional conventions on federal
matters in the United States have consistently failed because people are afraid
to open up the pandora's box of an unrestricted constitutional convention which
may attempt to "tamper with" constitutional provisions deemed sacred
by the country as a whole or by particular groups within it. Thus,
interpretation by the U.S. Supreme Court has become the most prevalent mode of
federal constitutional design used in the United States, a form which excludes
popular participation except at the very margins and which goes against the
spirit of modern constitutionalism as it was originally formulated.
Germany and the German-speaking countries have, for this reason,
attempted to utilize constitutional courts but to restrict the scope of their
activity by requiring the other institutions of government or the public at
large to participate in any processes of constitutional change. Nevertheless,
constitutional court interpretation is spreading as a form of constitutional
change in those countries as well as in many, if not most, others and the
American experience is looked upon admiringly and increasingly applied,
especially in the field of human and civil rights where more popular bodies are
less likely to expand the rights of individuals in the way the constitutional
courts will.
Interstate and Global Constitutional Arrangements
When modern federalism was first developed in the United States in the
eighteenth century, Europe was moving rapidly away from federalism in any form
toward the unitary centralized state, usually defined as a nation-state,
provided for in the international system established by the Treaty of
Westphalia (1648) at the very beginning of the modern epoch. The Westphalia
system provided for the principle of indivisible state sovereignty and all that
flowed from it, whereas federalism required what in statist terms was called
"divided sovereignty." In federalist terms this meant popular sovereignty
with governments not being sovereign but rather being the products of powers
delegated to them by the people, who could delegate whatever powers they wanted
to as many different governments as they wanted and still remain entirely
within the legitimate theoretical framework of federalism.
Indeed, the first American effort at modern federalism, the modern
confederation embodied in the Articles of Confederation, failed in part because
the way it attempted to divide sovereignty among governments went against the
spirit of the times. In its place the Americans substituted modern federation
whereby the United States appeared as a single nation to the outside world
while internally its people delegated powers to the federal and state
governments and through the state governments to local governments as well. This
"compromise" satisfied the demands (in some respect aesthetic
demands) of the larger world and enabled the United States to develop as a
single nation with a noncentralized political system over the next 200 years.
The American model of modern federation was frequently copied in the
nineteenth century and in some cases succeeded. In any case, the federation
model was so successful that it totally eclipsed any other forms of federalism
so that federalism and federation became, for all intents and purposes,
synonymous. Nevertheless, the necessities of other situations required the
application of federal principles in other ways in the twentieth century. Principal
among them were internal regionalization that became more than regional
decentralization as in Belgium, Italy, and Spain, and the development of
associated state relations between larger powers and smaller, usually offshore,
entities that demanded autonomy but did not seek or could not sustain full
independence, as in the case of the Netherlands and its Caribbean territories
or the United States and Puerto Rico.
These new forms of federalism spread rapidly after World War II when
they were joined by the revival of confederation and confederal arrangements,
albeit in a new style. Pioneering in this regard was the European Community,
now the European Union, after the federationist idea of the United States of
Europe fell by the wayside because of the strong separate identities of the
individual states. Western Europe was united through confederal devices which
were strengthened over the subsequent forty years until Western Europe more or
less formally became a confederation.
Other confederations and confederal arrangements emerged at the same
time or immediately thereafter. Moreover, federalism, which increasingly became
a form of political organization for the very largest countries, at least
nominally, began to spread to the smaller ones as well as individuals and
groups sought greater control over their immediate political environment while
at the same time needing to combine for security and economic purposes into
larger entities.
Each of the new federal arrangement required new forms and styles of
constitutional design, following but adapting old principles and models. Almost
all were begun with a political compact that was then followed by a
constitution (or constitutions, in some cases) embodying the rules, structures,
functions, and powers of the new federal arrangement. In both cases,
constitution referenda by one or both parties to the arrangements were
required.
At first the revival of federal arrangements was a matter for
individual states or nations and it was still possible to distinguish between
federal and unitary states or political systems. Beginning with the European
Community, initially a linkage of politically sovereign states by what was
formally a a network of treaties, that distinction began to diminish. Form the
first what was different about these treaties was that they were enforceable by
coming institutions and subject to the rulings of a common constitutional
court. France, perhaps the most unitary state of all, became part of the new
Western European confederation and was even forced to offer a degree of
constitutional autonomy to Corsica, not to speak of those of its overseas
territories that did not want or could not sustain independence. Moreover, when
Charles de Gaulle in one fell swoop abandoned France's African colonies, he did
so in such a manner that they were tied to their former mother country through
control of their currency and economic systems in an arrangement that was not
designated federal or even viewed as such by the participants and which was
confined to the economic and military sphere but which had at least
quasi-federal elements within it. Thirty years later, in the early 1990s, the
French used it to try to force greater democratization on community members in
Francophone Africa through refoundings via mutual conventions.
By the early 1990s, it was hard to find any state in the world that did
not have interstate ties that were more than simply treaty arrangements but
which were constitutionally entangling. Most of these arrangements remained
nominally open to unilateral dissolution but in practice few, if any, could be
dissolved without such great cost that none of their members would think of
dissolving them. This was particularly true in the economic sphere.
The General Agreement on Tariffs and Trade was formally no more than an
international treaty but, as the nations of the world came to realize during
the recently completed Uruguay round, not only was there no way for any single
country to leave GATT without paying a huge price but even regional blocs had
to learn how to accommodate one another within an improved and extended
agreement. On one hand, the worldwide GATT system had to be divided into
regional groupings and, on the other hand, the regional groupings learned how
to compromise with one another to maintain, renew, and extend the GATT
agreement. Indeed, at the conclusion of the long and exhausting Uruguay round,
the final document provided for the replacement of GATT with a World Trade
Organization (WTO) whose name already signified how far the constitutionalizing
process had gone beyond simply an international treaty to being a kind of
constitutional arrangement, however limited.
Thus another arena of federal arrangements is emerging, the
international arena, that goes beyond individual states, even large states. While
there is no talk of international federations, except among radical ideologues,
and these international relations have not reached the intricacy of confederal
arrangements, they are being constitutionalized, an extremely important step
that is causing every state in the international arena to constitutionally
recognize that exclusive state sovereignty is a thing of the past, that the
Westphalia system has collapsed, and that what was initially achieved, de
facto, as a result of the invention of nuclear weapons and the movement toward
greater economic interdependency is now acquiring a de jure dimension as well
so as to give it some regularization, stability, and to give the members of the
international community, as polities, as groups, and as individuals, some
measure of protection. This, too, has lead to new forms of constitutionalism
and constitutional design.
How far this will go and how it will get there cannot be foreseen at
this moment. There are too many imponderables and too many opportunities for
directions to shift, but what seems to be happening is that mechanisms are
emerging that have blurred the earlier distinctions between unitary and federal
states and their constituent units and citizens and to bring all together in
some increasingly, if only moderately, constitutionalized framework. This means
that the distinction between political scientists interested in international
relations and those interested in national or domestic affairs is also being
blurred. All of us in the profession need to pay due attention to these
changes.