公 法 评 论 http://www.gongfa.com/
Adam Smith
Part I
Of the Propriety of Action
Consisting of Three Sections
Section I Of the Sense of
Propriety
Chap. I Of Sympathy
ow selfish soever man may be supposed, there are evidently some principles in
his nature, which interest him in the fortune of others, and render their
happiness necessary to him, though he derives nothing from it except the
pleasure of seeing it. Of this kind is pity or compassion, the emotion which we
feel for the misery of others, when we either see it, or are made to conceive
it in a very lively manner. That we often derive sorrow from the sorrow of
others, is a matter of fact too obvious to require any instances to prove it;
for this sentiment, like all the other original passions of human nature, is by
no means confined to the virtuous and humane, though they perhaps may feel it
with the most exquisite sensibility. The greatest ruffian, the most hardened
violator of the laws of society, is not altogether without it.
I.I.1
As we have no immediate experience of what other men feel, we can form no idea
of the manner in which they are affected, but by conceiving what we ourselves
should feel in the like situation. Though our brother is upon the rack, as long
as we ourselves are at our ease, our senses will never inform us of what he
suffers. They never did, and never can, carry us beyond our own person, and it
is by the imagination only that we can form any conception of what are his
sensations. Neither can that faculty help us to this any other way, than by
representing to us what would be our own, if we were in his case. It is the
impressions of our own senses only, not those of his, which our imaginations
copy. By the imagination we place ourselves in his situation, we conceive
ourselves enduring all the same torments, we enter as it were into his body,
and become in some measure the same person with him, and thence form some idea
of his sensations, and even feel something which, though weaker in degree, is
not altogether unlike them. His agonies, when they are thus brought home to
ourselves, when we have thus adopted and made them our own, begin at last to
affect us, and we then tremble and shudder at the thought of what he feels. For
as to be in pain or distress of any kind excites the most excessive sorrow, so
to conceive or to imagine that we are in it, excites some degree of the same
emotion, in proportion to the vivacity or dulness of the conception.
I.I.2
That this is the source of our fellow-feeling for the misery of others, that it
is by changing places in fancy with the sufferer, that we come either to
conceive or to be affected by what he feels, may be demonstrated by many
obvious observations, if it should not be thought sufficiently evident of
itself. When we see a stroke aimed and just ready to fall upon the leg or arm
of another person, we naturally shrink and draw back our own leg or our own
arm; and when it does fall, we feel it in some measure, and are hurt by it as
well as the sufferer. The mob, when they are gazing at a dancer on the slack
rope, naturally writhe and twist and balance their own bodies, as they see him
do, and as they feel that they themselves must do if in his situation. Persons
of delicate fibres and a weak constitution of body complain, that in looking on
the sores and ulcers which are exposed by beggars in the streets, they are apt
to feel an itching or uneasy sensation in the correspondent part of their own
bodies. The horror which they conceive at the misery of those wretches affects
that particular part in themselves more than any other; because that horror
arises from conceiving what they themselves would suffer, if they really were
the wretches whom they are looking upon, and if that particular part in
themselves was actually affected in the same miserable manner. The very force
of this conception is sufficient, in their feeble frames, to produce that
itching or uneasy sensation complained of. Men of the most robust make, observe
that in looking upon sore eyes they often feel a very sensible soreness in
their own, which proceeds from the same reason; that organ being in the
strongest man more delicate, than any other part of the body is in the weakest.
I.I.3
Neither is it those circumstances only, which create pain or sorrow, that call
forth our fellow-feeling. Whatever is the passion which arises from any object
in the person principally concerned, an analogous emotion springs up, at the
thought of his situation, in the breast of every attentive spectator. Our joy
for the deliverance of those heroes of tragedy or romance who interest us, is
as sincere as our grief for their distress, and our fellow-feeling with their
misery is not more real than that with their happiness. We enter into their
gratitude towards those faithful friends who did not desert them in their
difficulties; and we heartily go along with their resentment against those
perfidious traitors who injured, abandoned, or deceived them. In every passion
of which the mind of man is susceptible, the emotions of the by-stander always
correspond to hat, by bringing the case home to himself, he imagines should be
the sentiments of the sufferer.
I.I.4
Pity and compassion are words appropriated to signify our fellow-feeling with
the sorrow of others. Sympathy, though its meaning was, perhaps, originally the
same, may now, however, without much impropriety, be made use of to denote our
fellow-feeling with any passion whatever.
I.I.5
Upon some occasions sympathy may seen to arise merely from the view of a
certain emotion in another person. The passions, upon some occasions, may seem
to be transfused from one man to another, instantaneously and antecedent to any
knowledge of what excited them in the person principally concerned. Grief and
joy, for example, strongly expressed in the look and gestures of any one, at
once affect the spectator with some degree of a like painful or agreeable
emotion. A smiling face is, to every body that sees it, a cheerful object; as a
sorrowful countenance, on the other hand, is a melancholy one.
I.I.6
This, however, does not hold universally, or with regard to every passion.
There are some passions of which the expressions excite no sort of sympathy,
but before we are acquainted with what gave occasion to them, serve rather to
disgust and provoke us against them. The furious behaviour of an angry man is
more likely to exasperate us against himself than against his enemies. As we
are unacquainted with his provocation, we cannot bring his case home to
ourselves, nor conceive any thing like the passions which it excites. But we
plainly see what is the situation of those with whom he is angry, and to what
violence they may be exposed from so enraged an adversary. We readily,
therefore, sympathize with their fear or resentment, and are immediately
disposed to take part against the man from whom they appear to be in so much
danger.
I.I.7
If the very appearances of grief and joy inspire us with some degree of the
like emotions, it is because they suggest to us the general idea of some good
or bad fortune that has befallen the person in whom we observe them: and in
these passions this is sufficient to have some little influence upon us. The
effects of grief and joy terminate in the person who feels those emotions, of
which the expressions do not, like those of resentment, suggest to us the idea
of any other person for whom we are concerned, and whose interests are opposite
to his. The general idea of good or bad fortune, therefore, creates some
concern for the person who has met with it, but the general idea of provocation
excites no sympathy with the anger of the man who has received it. Nature, it
seems, teaches us to be more averse to enter into this passion, and, till
informed of its cause, to be disposed rather to take part against it.
I.I.8
Even our sympathy with the grief or joy of another, before we are informed of
the cause of either, is always extremely imperfect. General lamentations, which
express nothing but the anguish of the sufferer, create rather a curiosity to
inquire into his situation, along with some disposition to sympathize with him,
than any actual sympathy that is very sensible. The first question which we ask
is, What has befallen you? Till this be answered, though we are uneasy both
from the vague idea of his misfortune, and still more from torturing ourselves
with conjectures about what it may be, yet our fellow-feeling is not very
considerable.
I.I.9
Sympathy, therefore, does not arise so much from the view of the passion, as
from that of the situation which excites it. We sometimes feel for another, a
passion of which he himself seems to be altogether incapable; because, when we
put ourselves in his case, that passion arises in our breast from the
imagination, though it does not in his from the reality. We blush for the
impudence and rudeness of another, though he himself appears to have no sense
of the impropriety of his own behaviour; because we cannot help feeling with what
confusion we ourselves should be covered, had we behaved in so absurd a manner.
I.I.10
Of all the calamities to which the condition of mortality exposes mankind, the
loss of reason appears, to those who have the least spark of humanity, by far
the most dreadful, and they behold that last stage of human wretchedness with
deeper commiseration than any other. But the poor wretch, who is in it, laughs
and sings perhaps, and is altogether insensible of his own misery. The anguish
which humanity feels, therefore, at the sight of such an object, cannot be the
reflection of any sentiment of the sufferer. The compassion of the spectator
must arise altogether from the consideration of what he himself would feel if
he was reduced to the same unhappy situation, and, what perhaps is impossible,
was at the same time able to regard it with his present reason and judgment.
I.I.11
What are the pangs of a mother, when she hears the moanings of her infant that
during the agony of disease cannot express what it feels? In her idea of what
it suffers, she joins, to its real helplessness, her own consciousness of that
helplessness, and her own terrors for the unknown consequences of its disorder;
and out of all these, forms, for her own sorrow, the most complete image of
misery and distress. The infant, however, feels only the uneasiness of the
present instant, which can never be great. With regard to the future, it is
perfectly secure, and in its thoughtlessness and want of foresight, possesses
an antidote against fear and anxiety, the great tormentors of the human breast,
from which reason and philosophy will, in vain, attempt to defend it, when it
grows up to a man.
I.I.12
We sympathize even with the dead, and overlooking what is of real importance in
their situation, that awful futurity which awaits them, we are chiefly affected
by those circumstances which strike our senses, but can have no influence upon
their happiness. It is miserable, we think, to be deprived of the light of the
sun; to be shut out from life and conversation; to be laid in the cold grave, a
prey to corruption and the reptiles of the earth; to be no more thought of in
this world, but to be obliterated, in a little time, from the affections, and
almost from the memory, of their dearest friends and relations. Surely, we
imagine, we can never feel too much for those who have suffered so dreadful a
calamity. The tribute of our fellow-feeling seems doubly due to them now, when
they are in danger of being forgot by every body; and, by the vain honours
which we pay to their memory, we endeavour, for our own misery, artificially to
keep alive our melancholy remembrance of their misfortune. That our sympathy
can afford them no consolation seems to be an addition to their calamity; and
to think that all we can do is unavailing, and that, what alleviates all other
distress, the regret, the love, and the lamentations of their friends, can
yield no comfort to them, serves only to exasperate our sense of their misery.
The happiness of the dead, however, most assuredly, is affected by none of
these circumstances; nor is it the thought of these things which can ever
disturb the profound security of their repose. The idea of that dreary and
endless melancholy, which the fancy naturally ascribes to their condition, arises
altogether from our joining to the change which has been produced upon them,
our own consciousness of that change, from our putting ourselves in their
situation, and from our lodging, if I may be allowed to say so, our own living
souls in their inanimated bodies, and thence conceiving what would be our
emotions in this case. It is from this very illusion of the imagination, that
the foresight of our own dissolution is so terrible to us, and that the idea of
those circumstances, which undoubtedly can give us no pain when we are dead,
makes us miserable while we are alive. And from thence arises one of the most
important principles in human nature, the dread of death, the great poison to
the happiness, but the great restraint upon the injustice of mankind, which,
while it afflicts and mortifies the individual, guards and protects the
society.
I.I.13
Chap. II Of the Pleasure of
mutual Sympathy
But whatever may be the cause of sympathy, or however it may be excited,
nothing pleases us more than to observe in other men a fellow-feeling with all
the emotions of our own breast; nor are we ever so much shocked as by the
appearance of the contrary. Those who are fond of deducing all our sentiments
from certain refinements of self-love, think themselves at no loss to account,
according to their own principles, both for this pleasure and this pain. Man,
say they, conscious of his own weakness, and of the need which he has for the
assistance of others, rejoices whenever he observes that they adopt his own
passions, because he is then assured of that assistance; and grieves whenever
he observes the contrary, because he is then assured of their opposition. But
both the pleasure and the pain are always felt so instantaneously, and often
upon such frivolous occasions, that it seems evident that neither of them can
be derived from any such self-interested consideration. A man is mortified
when, after having endeavoured to divert the company, he looks round and sees
that nobody laughs at his jests but himself. On the contrary, the mirth of the
company is highly agreeable to him, and he regards this correspondence of their
sentiments with his own as the greatest applause.
I.I.14
Neither does his pleasure seem to arise altogether from the additional vivacity
which his mirth may receive from sympathy with theirs, nor his pain from the
disappointment he meets with when he misses this pleasure; though both the one
and the other, no doubt, do in some measure. When we have read a book or poem
so often that we can no longer find any amusement in reading it by ourselves,
we can still take pleasure in reading it to a companion. To him it has all the
graces of novelty; we enter into the surprise and admiration which it naturally
excites in him, but which it is no longer capable of exciting in us; we
consider all the ideas which it presents rather in the light in which they
appear to him, than in that in which they appear to ourselves, and we are
amused by sympathy with his amusement which thus enlivens our own. On the contrary,
we should be vexed if he did not seem to be entertained with it, and we could
no longer take any pleasure in reading it to him. It is the same case here. The
mirth of the company, no doubt, enlivens our own mirth, and their silence, no
doubt, disappoints us. But though this may contribute both to the pleasure
which we derive from the one, and to the pain which we feel from the other, it
is by no means the sole cause of either; and this correspondence of the
sentiments of others with our own appears to be a cause of pleasure, and the
want of it a cause of pain, which cannot be accounted for in this manner. The
sympathy, which my friends express with my joy, might, indeed, give me pleasure
by enlivening that joy: but that which they express with my grief could give me
none, if it served only to enliven that grief. Sympathy, however, enlivens joy
and alleviates grief. It enlivens joy by presenting another source of
satisfaction; and it alleviates grief by insinuating into the heart almost the
only agreeable sensation which it is at that time capable of receiving.
I.I.15
It is to be observed accordingly, that we are still more anxious to communicate
to our friends our disagreeable than our agreeable passions, that we derive
still more satisfaction from their sympathy with the former than from that with
the latter, and that we are still more shocked by the want of it.
I.I.16
How are the unfortunate relieved when they have found out a person to whom they
can communicate the cause of their sorrow? Upon his sympathy they seem to
disburthen themselves of a part of their distress: he is not improperly said to
share it with them. He not only feels a sorrow of the same kind with that which
they feel, but as if he had derived a part of it to himself, what he feels
seems to alleviate the weight of what they feel. Yet by relating their
misfortunes they in some measure renew their grief. They awaken in their memory
the remembrance of those circumstances which occasioned their affliction. Their
tears accordingly flow faster than before, and they are apt to abandon
themselves to all the weakness of sorrow. They take pleasure, however, in all
this, and, it is evident, are sensibly relieved by it; because the sweetness of
his sympathy more than compensates the bitterness of that sorrow, which, in
order to excite this sympathy, they had thus enlivened and renewed. The
cruelest insult, on the contrary, which can be offered to the unfortunate, is
to appear to make light of their calamities. To seem not to be affected with
the joy of our companions is but want of politeness; but not to wear a serious
countenance when they tell us their afflictions, is real and gross inhumanity.
I.I.17
Love is an agreeable; resentment, a disagreeable passion; and accordingly we
are not half so anxious that our friends should adopt our friendships, as that
they should enter into our resentments. We can forgive them though they seem to
be little affected with the favours which we may have received, but lose all
patience if they seem indifferent about the injuries which may have been done
to us: nor are we half so angry with them for not entering into our gratitude,
as for not sympathizing with our resentment. They can easily avoid being
friends to our friends, but can hardly avoid being enemies to those with whom
we are at variance. We seldom resent their being at enmity with the first,
though upon that account we may sometimes affect to make an awkward quarrel
with them; but we quarrel with them in good earnest if they live in friendship with
the last. The agreeable passions of love and joy can satisfy and support the
heart without any auxiliary pleasure. The bitter and painful emotions of grief
and resentment more strongly require the healing consolation of sympathy.
I.I.18
As the person who is principally interested in any event is pleased with our
sympathy, and hurt by the want of it, so we, too, seem to be pleased when we
are able to sympathize with him, and to be hurt when we are unable to do so. We
run not only to congratulate the successful, but to condole with the afflicted;
and the pleasure which we find in the conversation of one whom in all the
passions of his heart we can entirely sympathize with, seems to do more than
compensate the painfulness of that sorrow with which the view of his situation
affects us. On the contrary, it is always disagreeable to feel that we cannot
sympathize with him, and instead of being pleased with this exemption from
sympathetic pain, it hurts us to find that we cannot share his uneasiness. If we
hear a person loudly lamenting his misfortunes, which, however, upon bringing
the case home to ourselves, we feel, can produce no such violent effect upon
us, we are shocked at his grief; and, because we cannot enter into it, call it
pusillanimity and weakness. It gives us the spleen, on the other hand, to see
another too happy or too much elevated, as we call it, with any little piece of
good fortune. We are disobliged even with his joy; and, because we cannot go
along with it, call it levity and folly. We are even put out of humour if our
companion laughs louder or longer at a joke than we think it deserves; that is,
than we feel that we ourselves could laugh at it.
I.I.19
Chap. III Of the manner in which
we judge of the propriety or impropriety of the affections of other men, by
their concord or dissonance with our own.
When the original passions of the person principally concerned are in perfect
concord with the sympathetic emotions of the spectator, they necessarily appear
to this last just and proper, and suitable to their objects; and, on the
contrary, when, upon bringing the case home to himself, he finds that they do
not coincide with what he feels, they necessarily appear to him unjust and
improper, and unsuitable to the causes which excite them. To approve of the
passions of another, therefore, as suitable to their objects, is the same thing
as to observe that we entirely sympathize with them; and not to approve of them
as such, is the same thing as to observe that we do not entirely sympathize
with them. The man who resents the injuries that have been done to me, and
observes that I resent them precisely as he does, necessarily approves of my
resentment. The man whose sympathy keeps time to my grief, cannot but admit the
reasonableness of my sorrow. He who admires the same poem, or the same picture,
and admires them exactly as I do, must surely allow the justness of my
admiration. He who laughs at the same joke, and laughs along with me, cannot
well deny the propriety of my laughter. On the contrary, the person who, upon
these different occasions, either feels no such emotion as that which I feel,
or feels none that bears any proportion to mine, cannot avoid disapproving my
sentiments on account of their dissonance with his own. If my animosity goes
beyond what the indignation of my friend can correspond to; if my grief exceeds
what his most tender compassion can go along with; if my admiration is either
too high or too low to tally with his own; if I laugh loud and heartily when he
only smiles, or, on the contrary, only smile when he laughs loud and heartily;
in all these cases, as soon as he comes from considering the object, to observe
how I am affected by it, according as there is more or less disproportion
between his sentiments and mine, I must incur a greater or less degree of his
disapprobation: and upon all occasions his own sentiments are the standards and
measures by which he judges of mine.
I.I.20
To approve of another man's opinions is to adopt those opinions, and to adopt them
is to approve of them. If the same arguments which convince you convince me
likewise, I necessarily approve of your conviction; and if they do not, I
necessarily disapprove of it: neither can I possibly conceive that I should do
the one without the other. To approve or disapprove, therefore, of the opinions
of others is acknowledged, by every body, to mean no more than to observe their
agreement or disagreement with our own. But this is equally the case with
regard to our approbation or disapprobation of the sentiments or passions of
others.
I.I.21
There are, indeed, some cases in which we seem to approve without any sympathy
or correspondence of sentiments, and in which, consequently, the sentiment of
approbation would seem to be different from the perception of this coincidence.
A little attention, however, will convince us that even in these cases our
approbation is ultimately founded upon a sympathy or correspondence of this
kind. I shall give an instance in things of a very frivolous nature, because in
them the judgments of mankind are less apt to be perverted by wrong systems. We
may often approve of a jest, and think the laughter of the company quite just
and proper, though we ourselves do not laugh, because, perhaps, we are in a
grave humour, or happen to have our attention engaged with other objects. We
have learned, however, from experience, what sort of pleasantry is upon most
occasions capable of making us laugh, and we observe that this is one of that
kind. We approve, therefore, of the laughter of the company, and feel that it
is natural and suitable to its object; because, though in our present mood we
cannot easily enter into it, we are sensible that upon most occasions we should
very heartily join in it.
I.I.22
The same thing often happens with regard to all the other passions. A stranger
passes by us in the street with all the marks of the deepest affliction; and we
are immediately told that he has just received the news of the death of his
father. It is impossible that, in this case, we should not approve of his
grief. Yet it may often happen, without any defect of humanity on our part,
that, so far from entering into the violence of his sorrow, we should scarce
conceive the first movements of concern upon his account. Both he and his
father, perhaps, are entirely unknown to us, or we happen to be employed about
other things, and do not take time to picture out in our imagination the
different circumstances of distress which must occur to him. We have learned,
however, from experience, that such a misfortune naturally excites such a
degree of sorrow, and we know that if we took time to consider his situation,
fully and in all its parts, we should, without doubt, most sincerely sympathize
with him. It is upon the consciousness of this conditional sympathy, that our
approbation of his sorrow is founded, even in those cases in which that
sympathy does not actually take place; and the general rules derived from our
preceding experience of what our sentiments would commonly correspond with,
correct upon this, as upon many other occasions, the impropriety of our present
emotions.
I.I.23
The sentiment or affection of the heart from which any action proceeds, and
upon which its whole virtue or vice must ultimately depend, may be considered
under two different aspects, or in two different relations; first, in relation
to the cause which excites it, or the motive which gives occasion to it; and
secondly, in relation to the end which it proposes, or the effect which it
tends to produce.
I.I.24
In the suitableness or unsuitableness, in the proportion or disproportion which
the affection seems to bear to the cause or object which excites it, consists
the propriety or impropriety, the decency or ungracefulness of the consequent
action.
I.I.25
In the beneficial or hurtful nature of the effects which the affection aims at,
or tends to produce, consists the merit or demerit of the action, the qualities
by which it is entitled to reward, or is deserving of punishment.
I.I.26
Philosophers have, of late years, considered chiefly the tendency of
affections, and have given little attention to the relation which they stand in
to the cause which excites them. In common life, however, when we judge of any
person's conduct, and of the sentiments which directed it, we constantly
consider them under both these aspects. When we blame in another man the
excesses of love, of grief, of resentment, we not only consider the ruinous
effects which they tend to produce, but the little occasion which was given for
them. The merit of his favourite, we say, is not so great, his misfortune is
not so dreadful, his provocation is not so extraordinary, as to justify so
violent a passion. We should have indulged, we say; perhaps, have approved of
the violence of his emotion, had the cause been in any respect proportioned to
it.
I.I.27
When we judge in this manner of any affection, as proportioned or
disproportioned to the cause which excites it, it is scarce possible that we
should make use of any other rule or canon but the correspondent affection in
ourselves. If, upon bringing the case home to our own breast, we find that the
sentiments which it gives occasion to, coincide and tally with our own, we
necessarily approve of them as proportioned and suitable to their objects; if
otherwise, we necessarily disapprove of them, as extravagant and out of
proportion.
I.I.28
Every faculty in one man is the measure by which he judges of the like faculty
in another. I judge of your sight by my sight, of your ear by my ear, of your
reason by my reason, of your resentment by my resentment, of your love by my
love. I neither have, nor can have, any other way of judging about them.
I.I.29
Chap. IV The same subject
continued
We may judge of the propriety or impropriety of the sentiments of another
person by their correspondence or disagreement with our own, upon two different
occasions; either, first, when the objects which excite them are considered
without any peculiar relation, either to ourselves or to the person whose
sentiments we judge of; or, secondly, when they are considered as peculiarly
affecting one or other of us.
I.I.30
1. With regard to those objects which are considered without any peculiar
relation either to ourselves or to the person whose sentiments we judge of;
wherever his sentiments entirely correspond with our own, we ascribe to him the
qualities of taste and good judgment. The beauty of a plain, the greatness of a
mountain, the ornaments of a building, the expression of a picture, the
composition of a discourse, the conduct of a third person, the proportions of
different quantities and numbers, the various appearances which the great
machine of the universe is perpetually exhibiting, with the secret wheels and
springs which product them; all the general subjects of science and taste, are
what we and our companion regard as having no peculiar relation to either of
us. We both look at them from the same point of view, and we have no occasion
for sympathy, or for that imaginary change of situations from which it arises,
in order to produce, with regard to these, the most perfect harmony of
sentiments and affections. If, notwithstanding, we are often differently
affected, it arises either from the different degrees of attention, which our different
habits of life allow us to give easily to the several parts of those complex
objects, or from the different degrees of natural acuteness in the faculty of
the mind to which they are addressed.
I.I.31
When the sentiments of our companion coincide with our own in things of this
kind, which are obvious and easy, and in which, perhaps, we never found a
single person who differed from us, though we, no doubt, must approve of them,
yet he seems to deserve no praise or admiration on account of them. But when
they not only coincide with our own, but lead and direct our own; when in
forming them he appears to have attended to many things which we had
overlooked, and to have adjusted them to all the various circumstances of their
objects; we not only approve of them, but wonder and are surprised at their
uncommon and unexpected acuteness and comprehensiveness, and he appears to
deserve a very high degree of admiration and applause. For approbation
heightened by wonder and surprise, constitutes the sentiment which is properly
called admiration, and of which applause is the natural expression. The
decision of the man who judges that exquisite beauty is preferable to the
grossest deformity, or that twice two are equal to four, must certainly be
approved of by all the world, but will not, surely, be much admired. It is the
acute and delicate discernment of the man of taste, who distinguishes the
minute, and scarce perceptible differences of beauty and deformity; it is the
comprehensive accuracy of the experienced mathematician, who unravels, with
ease, the most intricate and perplexed proportions; it is the great leader in
science and taste, the man who directs and conducts our own sentiments, the
extent and superior justness of whose talents astonish us with wonder and
surprise, who excites our admiration, and seems to deserve our applause: and
upon this foundation is grounded the greater part of the praise which is
bestowed upon what are called the intellectual virtues.
I.I.32
The utility of those qualities, it may be thought, is what first recommends
them to us; and, no doubt, the consideration of this, when we come to attend to
it, gives them a new value. Originally, however, we approve of another man's
judgment, not as something useful, but as right, as accurate, as agreeable to
truth and reality: and it is evident we attribute those qualities to it for no
other reason but because we find that it agrees with our own. Taste, in the
same manner, is originally approved of, not as useful, but as just, as delicate,
and as precisely suited to its object. The idea of the utility of all qualities
of this kind, is plainly an after-thought, and not what first recommends them
to our approbation.
I.I.33
2. With regard to those objects, which affect in a particular manner either
ourselves or the person whose sentiments we judge of, it is at once more
difficult to preserve this harmony and correspondence, and at the same time,
vastly more important. My companion does not naturally look upon the misfortune
that has befallen me, or the injury that has been done me, from the same point
of view in which I consider them. They affect me much more nearly. We do not
view them from the same station, as we do a picture, or a poem, or a system of
philosophy, and are, therefore, apt to be very differently affected by them.
But I can much more easily overlook the want of this correspondence of
sentiments with regard to such indifferent objects as concern neither me nor my
companion, than with regard to what interests me so much as the misfortune that
has befallen me, or the injury that has been done me. Though you despise that
picture, or that poem, or even that system of philosophy, which I admire, there
is little danger of our quarrelling upon that account. Neither of us can reasonably
be much interested about them. They ought all of them to be matters of great
indifference to us both; so that, though our opinions may be opposite, our
affections may still be very nearly the same. But it is quite otherwise with
regard to those objects by which either you or I are particularly affected.
Though your judgments in matters of speculation, though your sentiments in
matters of taste, are quite opposite to mine, I can easily overlook this
opposition; and if I have any degree of temper, I may still find some
entertainment in your conversation, even upon those very subjects. But if you
have either no fellow-feeling for the misfortunes I have met with, or none that
bears any proportion to the grief which distracts me; or if you have either no
indignation at the injuries I have suffered, or none that bears any proportion
to the resentment which transports me, we can no longer converse upon these
subjects. We become intolerable to one another. I can neither support your
company, nor you mine. You are confounded at my violence and passion, and I am
enraged at your cold insensibility and want of feeling.
I.I.34
In all such cases, that there may be some correspondence of sentiments between
the spectator and the person principally concerned, the spectator must, first
of all, endeavour, as much as he can, to put himself in the situation of the
other, and to bring home to himself every little circumstance of distress which
can possibly occur to the sufferer. He must adopt the whole case of his companion
with all its minutest incidents; and strive to render as perfect as possible,
that imaginary change of situation upon which his sympathy is founded.
I.I.35
After all this, however, the emotions of the spectator will still be very apt
to fall short of the violence of what is felt by the sufferer. Mankind, though
naturally sympathetic, never conceive, for what has befallen another, that
degree of passion which naturally animates the person principally concerned.
That imaginary change of situation, upon which their sympathy is founded, is
but momentary. The thought of their own safety, the thought that they
themselves are not really the sufferers, continually intrudes itself upon them;
and though it does not hinder them from conceiving a passion somewhat analogous
to what is felt by the sufferer, hinders them from conceiving any thing that
approaches to the same degree of violence. The person principally concerned is
sensible of this, and at the same time passionately desires a more complete
sympathy. He longs for that relief which nothing can afford him but the entire
concord of the affections of the spectators with his own. To see the emotions
of their hearts, in every respect, beat time to his own, in the violent and
disagreeable passions, constitutes his sole consolation. But he can only hope
to obtain this by lowering his passion to that pitch, in which the spectators
are capable of going along with him. He must flatten, if I may be allowed to
say so, the sharpness of its natural tone, in order to reduce it to harmony and
concord with the emotions of those who are about him. What they feel, will,
indeed, always be, in some respects, different from what he feels, and
compassion can never be exactly the same with original sorrow; because the
secret consciousness that the change of situations, from which the sympathetic
sentiment arises, is but imaginary, not only lowers it in degree, but, in some
measure, varies it in kind, and gives it a quite different modification. These
two sentiments, however, may, it is evident, have such a correspondence with
one another, as is sufficient for the harmony of society. Though they will
never be unisons, they may be concords, and this is all that is wanted or
required.
I.I.36
In order to produce this concord, as nature teaches the spectators to assume
the circumstances of the person principally concerned, so she teaches this last
in some measure to assume those of the spectators. As they are continually
placing themselves in his situation, and thence conceiving emotions similar to
what he feels; so he is as constantly placing himself in theirs, and thence
conceiving some degree of that coolness about his own fortune, with which he is
sensible that they will view it. As they are constantly considering what they
themselves would feel, if they actually were the sufferers, so he is as
constantly led to imagine in what manner he would be affected if he was only
one of the spectators of his own situation. As their sympathy makes them look
at it, in some measure, with his eyes, so his sympathy makes him look at it, in
some measure, with theirs, especially when in their presence and acting under
their observation: and as the reflected passion, which he thus conceives, is
much weaker than the original one, it necessarily abates the violence of what
he felt before he came into their presence, before he began to recollect in
what manner they would be affected by it, and to view his situation in this
candid and impartial light.
I.I.37
The mind, therefore, is rarely so disturbed, but that the company of a friend
will restore it to some degree of tranquillity and sedateness. The breast is,
in some measure, calmed and composed the moment we come into his presence. We
are immediately put in mind of the light in which he will view our situation,
and we begin to view it ourselves in the same light; for the effect of sympathy
is instantaneous. We expect less sympathy from a common acquaintance than from
a friend: we cannot open to the former all those little circumstances which we
can unfold to the latter: we assume, therefore, more tranquillity before him,
and endeavour to fix our thoughts upon those general outlines of our situation
which he is willing to consider. We expect still less sympathy from an assembly
of strangers, and we assume, therefore, still more tranquillity before them,
and always endeavour to bring down our passion to that pitch, which the
particular company we are in may be expected to go along with. Nor is this only
an assumed appearance: for if we are at all masters of ourselves, the presence
of a mere acquaintance will really compose us, still more than that of a
friend; and that of an assembly of strangers still more than that of an
acquaintance.
I.I.38
Society and conversation, therefore, are the most powerful remedies for
restoring the mind to its tranquillity, if, at any time, it has unfortunately
lost it; as well as the best preservatives of that equal and happy temper,
which is so necessary to self-satisfaction and enjoyment. Men of retirement and
speculation, who are apt to sit brooding at home over either grief or
resentment, though they may often have more humanity, more generosity, and a
nicer sense of honour, yet seldom possess that equality of temper which is so
common among men of the world.
I.I.39
Chap. V Of the amiable and respectable virtues
Upon these two different efforts, upon that of the spectator to enter into the
sentiments of the person principally concerned, and upon that of the person
principally concerned, to bring down his emotions to what the spectator can go
along with, are founded two different sets of virtues. The soft, the gentle,
the amiable virtues, the virtues of candid condescension and indulgent
humanity, are founded upon the one: the great, the awful and respectable, the
virtues of self-denial, of self-government, of that command of the passions
which subjects all the movements of our nature to what our own dignity and
honour, and the propriety of our own conduct require, take their origin from
the other.
I.I.40
How amiable does he appear to be, whose sympathetic heart seems to reecho all
the sentiments of those with whom he converses, who grieves for their
calamities, who resents their injuries, and who rejoices at their good fortune!
When we bring home to ourselves the situation of his companions, we enter into
their gratitude, and feel what consolation they must derive from the tender
sympathy of so affectionate a friend. And for a contrary reason, how
disagreeable does he appear to be, whose hard and obdurate heart feels for
himself only, but is altogether insensible to the happiness or misery of
others! We enter, in this case too, into the pain which his presence must give
to every mortal with whom he converses, to those especially with whom we are
most apt to sympathize, the unfortunate and the injured.
I.I.41
On the other hand, what noble propriety and grace do we feel in the conduct of
those who, in their own case, exert that recollection and self-command which
constitute the dignity of every passion, and which bring it down to what others
can enter into! We are disgusted with that clamorous grief, which, without any
delicacy, calls upon our compassion with sighs and tears and importunate
lamentations. But we reverence that reserved, that silent and majestic sorrow,
which discovers itself only in the swelling of the eyes, in the quivering of
the lips and cheeks, and in the distant, but affecting, coldness of the whole
behaviour. It imposes the like silence upon us. We regard it with respectful
attention, and watch with anxious concern over our whole behaviour, lest by any
impropriety we should disturb that concerted tranquillity, which it requires so
great an effort to support.
I.I.42
The insolence and brutality of anger, in the same manner, when we indulge its
fury without check or restraint, is, of all objects, the most detestable. But
we admire that noble and generous resentment which governs its pursuit of the
greatest injuries, not by the rage which they are apt to excite in the breast
of the sufferer, but by the indignation which they naturally call forth in that
of the impartial spectator; which allows no word, no gesture, to escape it
beyond what this more equitable sentiment would dictate; which never, even in
thought, attempts any greater vengeance, nor desires to inflict any greater
punishment, than what every indifferent person would rejoice to see executed.
I.I.43
And hence it is, that to feel much for others and little for ourselves, that to
restrain our selfish, and to indulge our benevolent affections, constitutes the
perfection of human nature; and can alone produce among mankind that harmony of
sentiments and passions in which consists their whole grace and propriety. As
to love our neighbour as we love ourselves is the great law of Christianity, so
it is the great precept of nature to love ourselves only as we love our
neighbour, or what comes to the same thing, as our neighbour is capable of
loving us.
I.I.44
As taste and good judgment, when they are considered as qualities which deserve
praise and admiration, are supposed to imply a delicacy of sentiment and an
acuteness of understanding not commonly to be met with; so the virtues of
sensibility and self-command are not apprehended to consist in the ordinary,
but in the uncommon degrees of those qualities. The amiable virtue of humanity
requires, surely, a sensibility, much beyond what is possessed by the rude
vulgar of mankind. The great and exalted virtue of magnanimity undoubtedly
demands much more than that degree of self-command, which the weakest of
mortals is capable of exerting. As in the common degree of the intellectual
qualities, there is no abilities; so in the common degree of the moral, there
is no virtue. Virtue is excellence, something uncommonly great and beautiful,
which rises far above what is vulgar and ordinary. The amiable virtues consist
in that degree of sensibility which surprises by its exquisite and unexpected
delicacy and tenderness. The awful and respectable, in that degree of
self-command which astonishes by its amazing superiority over the most
ungovernable passions of human nature.
I.I.45
There is, in this respect, a considerable difference between virtue and mere
propriety; between those qualities and actions which deserve to be admired and
celebrated, and those which simply deserve to be approved of. Upon many
occasions, to act with the most perfect propriety, requires no more than that
common and ordinary degree of sensibility or self-command which the most
worthless of mankind are possest of, and sometimes even that degree is not
necessary. Thus, to give a very low instance, to eat when we are hungry, is
certainly, upon ordinary occasions, perfectly right and proper, and cannot miss
being approved of as such by every body. Nothing, however, could be more absurd
than to say it was virtuous.
I.I.46
On the contrary, there may frequently be a considerable degree of virtue in
those actions which fall short of the most perfect propriety; because they may
still approach nearer to perfection than could well be expected upon occasions
in which it was so extremely difficult to attain it: and this is very often the
case upon those occasions which require the greatest exertions of self-command.
There are some situations which bear so hard upon human nature, that the
greatest degree of self-government, which can belong to so imperfect a creature
as man, is not able to stifle, altogether, the voice of human weakness, or
reduce the violence of the passions to that pitch of moderation, in which the
impartial spectator can entirely enter into them. Though in those cases,
therefore, the behaviour of the sufferer fall short of the most perfect
propriety, it may still deserve some applause, and even in a certain sense, may
be denominated virtuous. It may still manifest an effort of generosity and
magnanimity of which the greater part of men are incapable; and though it fails
of absolute perfection, it may be a much nearer approximation towards
perfection, than what, upon such trying occasions, is commonly either to be
found or to be expected.
I.I.47
In cases of this kind, when we are determining the degree of blame or applause
which seems due to any action, we very frequently make use of two different
standards. The first is the idea of complete propriety and perfection, which,
in those difficult situations, no human conduct ever did, or ever can come, up
to; and in comparison with which the actions of all men must for ever appear
blameable and imperfect. The second is the idea of that degree of proximity or
distance from this complete perfection, which the actions of the greater part
of men commonly arrive at. Whatever goes beyond this degree, how far soever it
may be removed from absolute perfection, seems to deserve applause; and
whatever falls short of it, to deserve blame.
I.I.48
It is in the same manner that we judge of the productions of all the arts which
address themselves to the imagination. When a critic examines the work of any
of the great masters in poetry or painting, he may sometimes examine it by an
idea of perfection, in his own mind, which neither that nor any other human
work will ever come up to; and as long as he compares it with this standard, he
can see nothing in it but faults and imperfections. But when he comes to
consider the rank which it ought to hold among other works of the same kind, he
necessarily compares it with a very different standard, the common degree of
excellence which is usually attained in this particular art; and when he judges
of it by this new measure, it may often appear to deserve the highest applause,
upon account of its approaching much nearer to perfection than the greater part
of those works which can be brought into competition with it.
I.I.49
Section II Of the Degrees of the
different Passions which are consistent with Propriety
Introduction
he propriety of every passion excited by objects peculiarly related to
ourselves, the pitch which the spectator can go along with, must lie, it is
evident, in a certain mediocrity. If the passion is too high, or if it is too
low, he cannot enter into it. Grief and resentment for private misfortunes and
injuries may easily, for example, be too high, and in the greater part of
mankind they are so. They may likewise, though this more rarely happens, be too
low. We denominate the excess, weakness and fury: and we call the defect
stupidity, insensibility, and want of spirit. We can enter into neither of
them, but are astonished and confounded to see them.
I.II.1
This mediocrity, however, in which the point of propriety consists, is
different in different passions. It is high in some, and low in others. There
are some passions which it is indecent to express very strongly, even upon
those occasions, in which it is acknowledged that we cannot avoid feeling them
in the highest degree. And there are others of which the strongest expressions
are upon many occasions extremely graceful, even though the passions themselves
do not, perhaps, arise so necessarily. The first are those passions with which,
for certain reasons, there is little or no sympathy: the second are those with
which, for other reasons, there is the greatest. And if we consider all the
different passions of human nature, we shall find that they are regarded as
decent, or indecent, just in proportion as mankind are more or less disposed to
sympathize with them.
I.II.2
Chap. I Of the Passions which take their origin from
the body
1. It is indecent to express any strong degree of those passions which arise
from a certain situation or disposition of the body; because the company, not
being in the same disposition, cannot be expected to sympathize with them.
Violent hunger, for example, though upon many occasions not only natural, but
unavoidable, is always indecent, and to eat voraciously is universally regarded
as a piece of ill manners. There is, however, some degree of sympathy, even
with hunger. It is agreeable to see our companions eat with a good appetite,
and all expressions of loathing are offensive. The disposition of body which is
habitual to a man in health, makes his stomach easily keep time, if I may be
allowed so coarse an expression, with the one, and not with the other. We can
sympathize with the distress it in the which excessive hunger occasions when we
read the description of journal of a siege, or of a sea voyage. We imagine
ourselves in the situation of the sufferers, and thence readily conceive the
grief, the fear and consternation, which must necessarily distract them. We
feel, ourselves, some degree of those passions, and therefore sympathize with
them: but as we do not grow hungry by reading the description, we cannot
properly, even in this case, be said to sympathize with their hunger.
I.II.3
It is the same case with the passion by which Nature unites the two sexes.
Though naturally the most furious of all the passions, all strong expressions
of it are upon every occasion indecent, even between persons in whom its most
complete indulgence is acknowledged by all laws, both human and divine, to be
perfectly innocent. There seems, however, to be some degree of sympathy even
with this passion. To talk to a woman as we would to a man is improper: it is
expected that their company should inspire us with more gaiety, more
pleasantry, and more attention; and an intire insensibility to the fair sex,
renders a man contemptible in some measure even to the men.
I.II.4
Such is our aversion for all the appetites which take their origin from the
body: all strong expressions of them are loathsome and disagreeable. According
to some ancient philosophers, these are the passions which we share in common
with the brutes, and which having no connexion with the characteristical
qualities of human nature, are upon that account beneath its dignity. But there
are many other passions which we share in common with the brutes, such as
resentment, natural affection, even gratitude, which do not, upon that account,
appear to be so brutal. The true cause of the peculiar disgust which we
conceive for the appetites of the body when we see them in other men, is that
we cannot enter into them. To the person himself who feels them, as soon as
they are gratified, the object that excited them ceases to be agreeable: even
its presence often becomes offensive to him; he looks round to no purpose for the
charm which transported him the moment before, and he can now as little enter
into his own passion as another person. When we have dined, we order the covers
to be removed; and we should treat in the same manner the objects of the most
ardent and passionate desires, if they were the objects of no other passions
but those which take their origin from the body.
I.II.5
In the command of those appetites of the body consists that virtue which is
properly called temperance. To restrain them within those bounds, which regard
to health and fortune prescribes, is the part of prudence. But to confine them
within those limits, which grace, which propriety, which delicacy, and modesty
require, is the office of temperance.
I.II.6
2. It is for the same reason that to cry out with bodily pain, how intolerable
soever, appears always unmanly and unbecoming. There is, however, a good deal
of sympathy even with bodily pain. If, as has already been observed, I see a
stroke aimed, and just ready to fall upon the leg, or arm, of another person, I
naturally shrink and draw back my own leg, or my own arm: and when it does
fall, I feel it in some measure, and am hurt by it as well as the sufferer. My
hurt, however, is, no doubt, excessively slight, and, upon that account, if he
makes any violent out-cry, as I cannot go along with him, I never fail to
despise him. And this is the case of all the passions which take their origin
from the body: they excite either no sympathy at all, or such a degree of it,
as is altogether disproportioned to the violence of what is felt by the
sufferer.
I.II.7
It is quite otherwise with those passions which take their origin from the
imagination. The frame of my body can be but little affected by the alterations
which are brought about upon that of my companion: but my imagination is more
ductile, and more readily assumes, if I may say so, the shape and configuration
of the imaginations of those with whom I am familiar. A disappointment in love,
or ambition, will, upon this account, call forth more sympathy than the
greatest bodily evil. Those passions arise altogether from the imagination. The
person who has lost his whole fortune, if he is in health, feels nothing in his
body. What he suffers is from the imagination only, which represents to him the
loss of his dignity, neglect from his friends, contempt from his enemies,
dependance, want, and misery, coming fast upon him; and we sympathize with him
more strongly upon this account, because our imaginations can more readily
mould themselves upon his imagination, than our bodies can mould themselves
upon his body.
I.II.8
The loss of a leg may generally be regarded as a more real calamity than the
loss of a mistress. It would be a ridiculous tragedy, however, of which the
catastrophe was to turn upon a loss of that kind. A misfortune of the other
kind, how frivolous soever it may appear to be, has given occasion to many a
fine one.
I.II.9
Nothing is so soon forgot as pain. The moment it is gone the whole agony of it
is over, and the thought of it can no longer give us any sort of disturbance.
We ourselves cannot then enter into the anxiety and anguish which we had before
conceived. An unguarded word from a friend will occasion a more durable
uneasiness. The agony which this creates is by no means over with the word.
What at first disturbs us is not the object of the senses, but the idea of the
imagination. As it is an idea, therefore, which occasions our uneasiness, till
time and other accidents have in some measure effaced it from our memory, the
imagination continues to fret and rankle within, from the thought of it.
I.II.10
Pain never calls forth any very lively sympathy unless it is accompanied with
danger. We sympathize with the fear, though not with the agony of the sufferer.
Fear, however, is a passion derived altogether from the imagination, which
represents, with an uncertainty and fluctuation that increases our anxiety, not
what we really feel, but what we may hereafter possibly suffer. The gout or the
tooth-ach, though exquisitely painful, excite very little sympathy; more
dangerous diseases, though accompanied with very little pain, excite the
highest.
I.II.11
Some people faint and grow sick at the sight of a chirurgical operation, and
that bodily pain which is occasioned by tearing the flesh, seems, in them, to
excite the most excessive sympathy. We conceive in a much more lively and
distinct manner the pain which proceeds from an external cause, than we do that
which arises from an internal disorder. I can scarce form an idea of the
agonies of my neighbour when he is tortured with the gout, or the stone; but I
have the clearest conception of what he must suffer from an incision, a wound,
or a fracture. The chief cause, however, why such objects produce such violent
effects upon us, is their novelty. One who has been witness to a dozen
dissections, and as many amputations, sees, ever after, all operations of this
kind with great indifference, and often with perfect insensibility. Though we
have read or seen represented more than five hundred tragedies, we shall seldom
feel so entire an abatement of our sensibility to the objects which they
represent to us.
I.II.12
In some of the Greek tragedies there is an attempt to excite compassion, by the
representation of the agonies of bodily pain. Philoctetes cries out and faints
from the extremity of his sufferings. Hippolytus and Hercules are both
introduced as expiring under the severest tortures, which, it seems, even the
fortitude of Hercules was incapable of supporting. In all these cases, however,
it is not the pain which interests us, but some other circumstances. It is not
the sore foot, but the solitude, of Philoctetes which affects us, and diffuses
over that charming tragedy, that romantic wildness, which is so agreeable to
the imagination. The agonies of Hercules and Hippolytus are interesting only
because we foresee that death is to be the consequence. If those heroes were to
recover, we should think the representation of their sufferings perfectly
ridiculous. What a tragedy would that be of which the distress consisted in a
colic. Yet no pain is more exquisite. These attempts to excite compassion by
the representation of bodily pain, may be regarded as among the greatest
breaches of decorum of which the Greek theatre has set the example.
I.II.13
The little sympathy which we feel with bodily pain is the foundation of the
propriety of constancy and patience in enduring it. The man, who under the
severest tortures allows no weakness to escape him, vents no groan, gives way
to no passion which we do not entirely enter into, commands our highest
admiration. His firmness enables him to keep time with our indifference and
insensibility. We admire and entirely go along with the magnanimous effort
which he makes for this purpose. We approve of his behaviour, and from our
experience of the common weakness of human nature, we are surprised, and wonder
how he should be able to act so as to deserve approbation. Approbation, mixed
and animated by wonder and surprise, constitutes the sentiment which is
properly called admiration, of which, applause is the natural expression, as
has already been observed.
I.II.14
Chap. II Of those Passions
which take their origin from a particular turn or habit of the Imagination
Even of the passions derived from the imagination, those which take their
origin from a peculiar turn or habit it has acquired, though they may be
acknowledged to be perfectly natural, are, however, but little sympathized
with. The imaginations of mankind, not having acquired that particular turn,
cannot enter into them; and such passions, though they may be allowed to be
almost unavoidable in some part of life, are always, in some measure,
ridiculous. This is the case with that strong attachment which naturally grows
up between two persons of different sexes, who have long fixed their thoughts
upon one another. Our imagination not having run in the same channel with that
of the lover, we cannot enter into the eagerness of his emotions. If our friend
has been injured, we readily sympathize with his resentment, and grow angry
with the very person with whom he is angry. If he has received a benefit, we
readily enter into his gratitude, and have a very high sense of the merit of
his benefactor. But if he is in love, though we may think his passion just as
reasonable as any of the kind, yet we never think ourselves bound to conceive a
passion of the same kind, and for the same person for whom he has conceived it.
The passion appears to every body, but the man who feels it, entirely
disproportioned to the value of the object; and love, though it is pardoned in
a certain age because we know it is natural, is always laughed at, because we
cannot enter into it. All serious and strong expressions of it appear
ridiculous to a third person; and though a lover may be good company to his
mistress, he is so to nobody else. He himself is sensible of this; and as long
as he continues in his sober senses, endeavours to treat his own passion with
raillery and ridicule. It is the only style in which we care to hear of it;
because it is the only style in which we ourselves are disposed to talk of it.
We grow weary of the grave, pedantic, and long-sentenced love of Cowley and
Petrarca, who never have done with exaggerating the violence of their
attachments; but the gaiety of Ovid, and the gallantry of Horace, are always
agreeable.
I.II.15
But though we feel no proper sympathy with an attachment of this kind, though
we never approach even in imagination towards conceiving a passion for that
particular person, yet as we either have conceived, or may be disposed to
conceive, passions of the same kind, we readily enter into those high hopes of
happiness which are proposed from its gratification, as well as into that
exquisite distress which is feared from its disappointment. It interests us not
as a passion, but as a situation that gives occasion to other passions which
interest us; to hope, to fear, and to distress of every kind: in the same
manner as in a description of a sea voyage, it is not the hunger which
interests us, but the distress which that hunger occasions. Though we do not
properly enter into the attachment of the lover, we readily go along with those
expectations of romantic happiness which he derives from it. We feel how natural
it is for the mind, in a certain situation, relaxed with indolence, and
fatigued with the violence of desire, to long for serenity and quiet, to hope
to find them in the gratification of that passion which distracts it, and to
frame to itself the idea of that life of pastoral tranquillity and retirement
which the elegant, the tender, and the passionate Tibullus takes so much
pleasure in describing; a life like what the poets describe in the Fortunate
Islands, a life of friendship, liberty, and repose; free from labour, and from
care, and from all the turbulent passions which attend them. Even scenes of
this kind interest us most, when they are painted rather as what is hoped, than
as what is enjoyed. The grossness of that passion, which mixes with, and is,
perhaps, the foundation of love, disappears when its gratification is far off
and at a distance; but renders the whole offensive, when described as what is
immediately possessed. The happy passion, upon this account, interests us much
less than the fearful and the melancholy. We tremble for whatever can
disappoint such natural and agreeable hopes: and thus enter into all the
anxiety, and concern, and distress of the lover.
I.II.16
Hence it is, that, in some modern tragedies and romances, this passion appears
so wonderfully interesting. It is not so much the love of Castalio and Monimia
which attaches us in the Orphan, as the distress which that love occasions. The
author who should introduce two lovers, in a scene of perfect security,
expressing their mutual fondness for one another, would excite laughter, and
not sympathy. If a scene of this kind is ever admitted into a tragedy, it is
always, in some measure, improper, and is endured, not from any sympathy with
the passion that is expressed in it, but from concern for the dangers and
difficulties with which the audience foresee that its gratification is likely
to be attended.
I.II.17
The reserve which the laws of society impose upon the fair sex, with regard to
this weakness, renders it more peculiarly distressful in them, and, upon that
very account, more deeply interesting. We are charmed with the love of Phaedra,
as it is expressed in the French tragedy of that name, notwithstanding all the
extravagance and guilt which attend it. That very extravagance and guilt may be
said, in some measure, to recommend it to us. Her fear, her shame, her remorse,
her horror, her despair, become thereby more natural and interesting. All the
secondary passions, if I may be allowed to call them so, which arise from the
situation of love, become necessarily more furious and violent; and it is with
these secondary passions only that we can properly be said to sympathize.
I.II.18
Of all the passions, however, which are so extravagantly disproportioned to the
value of their objects, love is the only one that appears, even to the weakest
minds, to have any thing in it that is either graceful or agreeable. In itself,
first of all, though it may be ridiculous, it is not naturally odious; and
though its consequences are often fatal and dreadful, its intentions are seldom
mischievous. And then, though there is little propriety in the passion itself,
there is a good deal in some of those which always accompany it. There is in
love a strong mixture of humanity, generosity, kindness, friendship, esteem;
passions with which, of all others, for reasons which shall be explained
immediately, we have the greatest propensity to sympathize, even
notwithstanding we are sensible that they are, in some measure, excessive. The
sympathy which we feel with them, renders the passion which they accompany less
disagreeable, and supports it in our imagination, notwithstanding all the vices
which commonly go along with it; though in the one sex it necessarily leads to
the last ruin and infamy; and though in the other, where it is apprehended to
be least fatal, it is almost always attended with an incapacity for labour, a
neglect of duty, a contempt of fame, and even of common reputation.
Notwithstanding all this, the degree of sensibility and generosity with which
it is supposed to be accompanied, renders it to many the object of vanity. and
they are fond of appearing capable of feeling what would do them no honour if
they had really felt it.
I.II.19
It is for a reason of the same kind, that a certain reserve is necessary when
we talk of our own friends, our own studies, our own professions. All these are
objects which we cannot expect should interest our companions in the same
degree in which they interest us. And it is for want of this reserve, that the
one half of mankind make bad company to the other. A philosopher is company to
a philosopher, only. the member of a club, to his own little knot of
companions.
I.II.20
Chap. III Of the unsocial
Passions
There is another set of passions, which, though derived from the imagination,
yet before we can enter into them, or regard them as graceful or becoming, must
always be brought down to a pitch much lower than that to which undisciplined
nature would raise them. These are, hatred and resentment, with all their
different modifications. With regard to all such passions, our sympathy is
divided between the person who feels them, and the person who is the object of
them. The interests of these two are directly opposite. What our sympathy with
the person who feels them would prompt us to wish for, our fellow-feeling with
the other would lead us to fear. As they are both men, we are concerned for
both, and our fear for what the one may suffer, damps our resentment for what
the other has suffered. Our sympathy, therefore, with the man who has received
the provocation, necessarily falls short of the passion which naturally
animates him, not only upon account of those general causes which render all
sympathetic passions inferior to the original ones, but upon account of that
particular cause which is peculiar to itself, our opposite sympathy with
another person. Before resentment, therefore, can become graceful and
agreeable, it must be more humbled and brought down below that pitch to which it
would naturally rise, than almost any other passion.
I.II.21
Mankind, at the same time, have a very strong sense of the injuries that are
done to another. The villain, in a tragedy or romance, is as much the object of
our indignation, as the hero is that of our sympathy and affection. We detest
Iago as much as we esteem Othello; and delight as much in the punishment of the
one, as we are grieved at the distress of the other. But though mankind have so
strong a fellow-feeling with the injuries that are done to their brethren, they
do not always resent them the more that the sufferer appears to resent them.
Upon most occasions, the greater his patience, his mildness, his humanity,
provided it does not appear that he wants spirit, or that fear was the motive
of his forbearance, the higher their resentment against the person who injured
him. The amiableness of the character exasperates their sense of the atrocity
of the injury.
I.II.22
Those passions, however, are regarded as necessary parts of the character of
human nature. A person becomes contemptible who tamely sits still, and submits
to insults, without attempting either to repel or to revenge them. We cannot
enter into his indifference and insensibility. we call his behaviour
mean-spiritedness, and are as really provoked by it as by the insolence of his
adversary. Even the mob are enraged to see any man submit patiently to affronts
and ill usage. They desire to see this insolence resented, and resented by the
person who suffers from it. They cry to him with fury, to defend, or to revenge
himself. If his indignation rouses at last, they heartily applaud, and
sympathize with it. It enlivens their own indignation against his enemy, whom
they rejoice to see him attack in his turn, and are as really gratified by his
revenge, provided it is not immoderate, as if the injury had been done to
themselves.
I.II.23
But though the utility of those passions to the individual, by rendering it
dangerous to insult or injure him, be acknowledged; and though their utility to
the public, as the guardians of justice, and of the equality of its
administration, be not less considerable, as shall be shewn hereafter; yet
there is still something disagreeable in the passions themselves, which makes
the appearance of them in other men the natural object of our aversion. The
expression of anger towards any body present, if it exceeds a bare intimation
that we are sensible of his ill usage, is regarded not only as an insult to
that particular person, but as a rudeness to the whole company. Respect for
them ought to have restrained us from giving way to so boisterous and offensive
an emotion. It is the remote effects of these passions which are agreeable; the
immediate effects are mischief to the person against whom they are directed.
But it is the immediate, and not the remote effects of objects which render
them agreeable or disagreeable to the imagination. A prison is certainly more
useful to the public than a palace; and the person who founds the one is
generally directed by a much juster spirit of patriotism, than he who builds
the other. But the immediate effects of a prison, the confinement of the
wretches shut up in it, are disagreeable; and the imagination either does not
take time to trace out the remote ones, or sees them at too great a distance to
be much affected by them. A prison, therefore, will always be a disagreeable
object; and the fitter it is for the purpose for which it was intended, it will
be the more so. A palace, on the contrary, will always be agreeable; yet its
remote effects may often be inconvenient to the public. It may serve to promote
luxury, and set the example of the dissolution of manners. Its immediate
effects, however, the conveniency, the pleasure, and the gaiety of the people
who live in it, being all agreeable, and suggesting to the imagination a
thousand agreeable ideas, that faculty generally rests upon them, and seldom
goes further in tracing its more distant consequences. Trophies of the
instruments of music or of agriculture, imitated in painting or in stucco, make
a common and an agreeable ornament of our halls and dining-rooms. A trophy of
the same kind, composed of the instruments of surgery, of dissecting and
amputation-knives, of saws for cutting the bones, of trepanning instruments,
etc. would be absurd and shocking. Instruments of surgery, however, are always
more finely polished, and generally more nicely adapted to the purposes for
which they are intended, than instruments of agriculture. The remote effects of
them too, the health of the patient, is agreeable; yet as the immediate effect
of them is pain and suffering, the sight of them always displeases us.
Instruments of war are agreeable, though their immediate effect may seem to be
in the same manner pain and suffering. But then it is the pain and suffering of
our enemies, with whom we have no sympathy. With regard to us, they are
immediately connected with the agreeable ideas of courage, victory, and honour.
They are themselves, therefore, supposed to make one of the noblest parts of
dress, and the imitation of them one of the finest ornaments of architecture.
It is the same case with the qualities of the mind. The ancient stoics were of
opinion, that as the world was governed by the all-ruling providence of a wise,
powerful, and good God, every single event ought to be regarded, as making a
necessary part of the plan of the universe, and as tending to promote the
general order and happiness of the whole: that the vices and follies of
mankind, therefore, made as necessary a part of this plan as their wisdom or
their virtue; and by that eternal art which educes good from ill, were made to
tend equally to the prosperity and perfection of the great system of nature. No
speculation of this kind, however, how deeply soever it might be rooted in the
mind, could diminish our natural abhorrence for vice, whose immediate effects
are so destructive, and whose remote ones are too distant to be traced by the
imagination.
I.II.24
It is the same case with those passions we have been just now considering.
Their immediate effects are so disagreeable, that even when they are most
justly provoked, there is still something about them which disgusts us. These,
therefore, are the only passions of which the expressions, as I formerly
observed, do not dispose and prepare us to sympathize with them, before we are
informed of the cause which excites them. The plaintive voice of misery, when
heard at a distance, will not allow us to be indifferent about the person from
whom it comes. As soon as it strikes our ear, it interests us in his fortune,
and, if continued, forces us almost involuntarily to fly to his assistance. The
sight of a smiling countenance, in the same manner, elevates even the pensive
into that gay and airy mood, which disposes him to sympathize with, and share
the joy which it expresses; and he feels his heart, which with thought and care
was before that shrunk and depressed, instantly expanded and elated. But it is
quite otherwise with the expressions of hatred and resentment. The hoarse, boisterous,
and discordant voice of anger, when heard at a distance, inspires us either
with fear or aversion. We do not fly towards it, as to one who cries out with
pain and agony. Women, and men of weak nerves, tremble and are overcome with
fear, though sensible that themselves are not the objects of the anger. They
conceive fear, however, by putting themselves in the situation of the person
who is so. Even those of stouter hearts are disturbed; not indeed enough to
make them afraid, but enough to make them angry; for anger is the passion which
they would feel in the situation of the other person. It is the same case with
hatred. Mere expressions of spite inspire it against nobody, but the man who
uses them. Both these passions are by nature the objects of our aversion. Their
disagreeable and boisterous appearance never excites, never prepares, and often
disturbs our sympathy. Grief does not more powerfully engage and attract us to
the person in whom we observe it, than these, while we are ignorant of their
cause, disgust and detach us from him. It was, it seems, the intention of
Nature, that those rougher and more unamiable emotions, which drive men from
one another, should be less easily and more rarely communicated.
I.II.25
When music imitates the modulations of grief or joy, it either actually
inspires us with those passions, or at least puts us in the mood which disposes
us to conceive them. But when it imitates the notes of anger, it inspires us
with fear. Joy, grief, love, admiration, devotion, are all of them passions
which are naturally musical. Their natural tones are all soft, clear, and
melodious; and they naturally express themselves in periods which are
distinguished by regular pauses, and which upon that account are easily adapted
to the regular returns of the correspondent airs of a tune. The voice of anger,
on the contrary, and of all the passions which are akin to it, is harsh and
discordant. Its periods too are all irregular, sometimes very long, and
sometimes very short, and distinguished by no regular pauses. It is with
difficulty, therefore, that music can imitate any of those passions; and the
music which does imitate them is not the most agreeable. A whole entertainment
may consist, without any impropriety, of the imitation of the social and
agreeable passions. It would be a strange entertainment which consisted
altogether of the imitations of hatred and resentment.
I.II.26
If those passions are disagreeable to the spectator, they are not less so to
the person who feels them. Hatred and anger are the greatest poison to the
happiness of a good mind. There is, in the very feeling of those passions,
something harsh, jarring, and convulsive, something that tears and distracts
the breast, and is altogether destructive of that composure and tranquillity of
mind which is so necessary to happiness, and which is best promoted by the
contrary passions of gratitude and love. It is not the value of what they lose
by the perfidy and ingratitude of those they live with, which the generous and humane
are most apt to regret. Whatever they may have lost, they can generally be very
happy without it. What most disturbs them is the idea of perfidy and
ingratitude exercised towards themselves; and the discordant and disagreeable
passions which this excites, constitute, in their own opinion, the chief part
of the injury which they suffer.
I.II.27
How many things are requisite to render the gratification of resentment
completely agreeable, and to make the spectator thoroughly sympathize with our
revenge? The provocation must first of all be such that we should become
contemptible, and be exposed to perpetual insults, if we did not, in some
measure, resent it. Smaller offences are always better neglected; nor is there
any thing more despicable than that froward and captious humour which takes
fire upon every slight occasion of quarrel. We should resent more from a sense
of the propriety of resentment, from a sense that mankind expect and require it
of us, than because we feel in ourselves the furies of that disagreeable
passion. There is no passion, of which the human mind is capable, concerning
whose justness we ought to be so doubtful, concerning whose indulgence we ought
so carefully to consult our natural sense of propriety, or so diligently to
consider what will be the sentiments of the cool and impartial spectator.
Magnanimity, or a regard to maintain our own rank and dignity in society, is
the only motive which can ennoble the expressions of this disagreeable passion.
This motive must characterize our whole stile and deportment. These must be
plain, open, and direct; determined without positiveness, and elevated without
insolence; not only free from petulance and low scurrility, but generous,
candid, and full of all proper regards, even for the person who has offended
us. It must appear, in short, from our whole manner, without our labouring
affectedly to express it, that passion has not extinguished our humanity; and
that if we yield to the dictates of revenge, it is with reluctance, from
necessity, and in consequence of great and repeated provocations. When
resentment is guarded and qualified in this manner, it may be admitted to be
even generous and noble.
I.II.28
Chap. IV Of the social Passions
As it is a divided sympathy which renders the whole set of passions just now
mentioned, upon most occasions, so ungraceful and disagreeable; so there is
another set opposite to these, which a redoubled sympathy renders almost always
peculiarly agreeable and becoming. Generosity, humanity, kindness, compassion,
mutual friendship and esteem, all the social and benevolent affections, when
expressed in the countenance or behaviour, even towards those who are not
peculiarly connected with ourselves, please the indifferent spectator upon
almost every occasion. His sympathy with the person who feels those passions,
exactly coincides with his concern for the person who is the object of them.
The interest, which, as a man, he is obliged to take in the happiness of this
last, enlivens his fellow-feeling with the sentiments of the other, whose
emotions are employed about the same object. We have always, therefore, the
strongest disposition to sympathize with the benevolent affections. They appear
in every respect agreeable to us. We enter into the satisfaction both of the
person who feels them, and of the person who is the object of them. For as to
be the object of hatred and indignation gives more pain than all the evil which
a brave man can fear from his enemies; so there is a satisfaction in the
consciousness of being beloved, which, to a person of delicacy and sensibility,
is of more importance to happiness, than all the advantage which he can expect
to derive from it. What character is so detestable as that of one who takes
pleasure to sow dissension among friends, and to turn their most tender love
into mortal hatred? Yet wherein does the atrocity of this so much abhorred
injury consist? Is it in depriving them of the frivolous good offices, which,
had their friendship continued, they might have expected from one another? It
is in depriving them of that friendship itself, in robbing them of each other's
affections, from which both derived so much satisfaction; it is in disturbing
the harmony of their hearts, and putting an end to that happy commerce which had
before subsisted between them. These affections, that harmony, this commerce,
are felt, not only by the tender and the delicate, but by the rudest vulgar of
mankind, to be of more importance to happiness than all the little services
which could be expected to flow from them.
I.II.29
The sentiment of love is, in itself, agreeable to the person who feels it. It
sooths and composes the breast, seems to favour the vital motions, and to
promote the healthful state of the human constitution; and it is rendered still
more delightful by the consciousness of the gratitude and satisfaction which it
must excite in him who is the object of it. Their mutual regard renders them
happy in one another, and sympathy, with this mutual regard, makes them
agreeable to every other person. With what pleasure do we look upon a family,
through the whole of which reign mutual love and esteem, where the parents and
children are companions for one another, without any other difference than what
is made by respectful affection on the one side, and kind indulgence on the
other. where freedom and fondness, mutual raillery and mutual kindness, show
that no opposition of interest divides the brothers, nor any rivalship of
favour sets the sisters at variance, and where every thing presents us with the
idea of peace, cheerfulness, harmony, and contentment? On the contrary, how
uneasy are we made when we go into a house in which jarring contention sets one
half of those who dwell in it against the other; where amidst affected
smoothness and complaisance, suspicious looks and sudden starts of passion
betray the mutual jealousies which burn within them, and which are every moment
ready to burst out through all the restraints which the presence of the company
imposes?
I.II.30
Those amiable passions, even when they are acknowledged to be excessive, are
never regarded with aversion. There is something agreeable even in the weakness
of friendship and humanity. The too tender mother, the too indulgent father,
the too generous and affectionate friend, may sometimes, perhaps, on account of
the softness of their natures, be looked upon with a species of pity, in which,
however, there is a mixture of love, but can never be regarded with hatred and
aversion, nor even with contempt, unless by the most brutal and worthless of
mankind. It is always with concern, with sympathy and kindness, that we blame
them for the extravagance of their attachment. There is a helplessness in the
character of extreme humanity which more than any thing interests our pity.
There is nothing in itself which renders it either ungraceful or disagreeable.
We only regret that it is unfit for the world, because the world is unworthy of
it, and because it must expose the person who is endowed with it as a prey to
the perfidy and ingratitude of insinuating falsehood, and to a thousand pains
and uneasinesses, which, of all men, he the least deserves to feel, and which
generally too he is, of all men, the least capable of supporting. It is quite
otherwise with hatred and resentment. Too violent a propensity to those
detestable passions, renders a person the object of universal dread and
abhorrence, who, like a wild beast, ought, we think, to be hunted out of all
civil society.
I.II.31
Chap. V Of the selfish Passions
Besides those two opposite sets of passions, the social and unsocial, there is
another which holds a sort of middle place between them; is never either so
graceful as is sometimes the one set, nor is ever so odious as is sometimes the
other. Grief and joy, when conceived upon account of our own private good or
bad fortune, constitute this third set of passions. Even when excessive, they
are never so disagreeable as excessive resentment, because no opposite sympathy
can ever interest us against them: and when most suitable to their objects,
they are never so agreeable as impartial humanity and just benevolence; because
no double sympathy can ever interest us for them. There is, however, this
difference between grief and joy, that we are generally most disposed to sympathize
with small joys and great sorrows. The man who, by some sudden revolution of
fortune, is lifted up all at once into a condition of life, greatly above what
he had formerly lived in, may be assured that the congratulations of his best
friends are not all of them perfectly sincere. An upstart, though of the
greatest merit, is generally disagreeable, and a sentiment of envy commonly
prevents us from heartily sympathizing with his joy. If he has any judgment, he
is sensible of this, and instead of appearing to be elated with his good
fortune, he endeavours, as much as he can, to smother his joy, and keep down
that elevation of mind with which his new circumstances naturally inspire him.
He affects the same plainness of dress, and the same modesty of behaviour,
which became him in his former station. He redoubles his attention to his old
friends, and endeavours more than ever to be humble, assiduous, and
complaisant. And this is the behaviour which in his situation we most approve
of; because we expect, it seems, that he should have more sympathy with our
envy and aversion to his happiness, than we have with his happiness. It is
seldom that with all this he succeeds. We suspect the sincerity of his
humility, and he grows weary of this constraint. In a little time, therefore,
he generally leaves all his old friends behind him, some of the meanest of them
excepted, who may, perhaps, condescend to become his dependents: nor does he
always acquire any new ones; the pride of his new connections is as much affronted
at finding him their equal, as that of his old ones had been by his becoming
their superior: and it requires the most obstinate and persevering modesty to
atone for this mortification to either. He generally grows weary too soon, and
is provoked, by the sullen and suspicious pride of the one, and by the saucy
contempt of the other, to treat the first with neglect, and the second with
petulance, till at last he grows habitually insolent, and forfeits the esteem
of all. If the chief part of human happiness arises from the consciousness of
being beloved, as I believe it does, those sudden changes of fortune seldom
contribute much to happiness. He is happiest who advances more gradually to
greatness, whom the public destines to every step of his preferment long before
he arrives at it, in whom, upon that account, when it comes, it can excite no
extravagant joy, and with regard to whom it cannot reasonably create either any
jealousy in those he overtakes, or any envy in those he leaves behind.
I.II.32
Mankind, however, more readily sympathize with those smaller joys which flow
from less important causes. It is decent to be humble amidst great prosperity;
but we can scarce express too much satisfaction in all the little occurrences
of common life, in the company with which we spent the evening last night, in
the entertainment that was set before us, in what was said and what was done,
in all the little incidents of the present conversation, and in all those
frivolous nothings which fill up the void of human life. Nothing is more
graceful than habitual cheerfulness, which is always founded upon a peculiar
relish for all the little pleasures which common occurrences afford. We readily
sympathize with it: it inspires us with the same joy, and makes every trifle
turn up to us in the same agreeable aspect in which it presents itself to the
person endowed with this happy disposition. Hence it is that youth, the season
of gaiety, so easily engages our affections. That propensity to joy which seems
even to animate the bloom, and to sparkle from the eyes of youth and beauty,
though in a person of the same sex, exalts, even the aged, to a more joyous
mood than ordinary. They forget, for a time, their infirmities, and abandon
themselves to those agreeable ideas and emotions to which they have long been
strangers, but which, when the presence of so much happiness recalls them to
their breast, take their place there, like old acquaintance, from whom they are
sorry to have ever been parted, and whom they embrace more heartily upon
account of this long separation.
I.II.33
It is quite otherwise with grief. Small vexations excite no sympathy, but deep
affliction calls forth the greatest. The man who is made uneasy by every little
disagreeable incident, who is hurt if either the cook or the butler have failed
in the least article of their duty, who feels every defect in the highest
ceremonial of politeness, whether it be shewn to himself or to any other
person, who takes it amiss that his intimate friend did not bid him good-morrow
when they met in the forenoon, and that his brother hummed a tune all the time
he himself was telling a story; who is put out of humour by the badness of the
weather when in the country, by the badness of the roads when upon a journey,
and by the want of company, and dulness of all public diversions when in town;
such a person, I say, though he should have some reason, will seldom meet with
much sympathy. Joy is a pleasant emotion, and we gladly abandon ourselves to it
upon the slightest occasion. We readily, therefore, sympathize with it in
others, whenever we are not prejudiced by envy. But grief is painful, and the
mind, even when it is our own misfortune, naturally resists and recoils from
it. We would endeavour either not to conceive it at all, or to shake it off as
soon as we have conceived it. Our aversion to grief will not, indeed, always
hinder us from conceiving it in our own case upon very trifling occasions, but
it constantly prevents us from sympathizing with it in others when excited by the
like frivolous causes: for our sympathetic passions are always less
irresistible than our original ones. There is, besides, a malice in mankind,
which not only prevents all sympathy with little uneasinesses, but renders them
in some measure diverting. Hence the delight which we all take in raillery, and
in the small vexation which we observe in our companion, when he is pushed, and
urged, and teased upon all sides. Men of the most ordinary good-breeding
dissemble the pain which any little incident may give them; and those who are
more thoroughly formed to society, turn, of their own accord, all such
incidents into raillery, as they know their companions will do for them. The
habit which a man, who lives in the world, has acquired of considering how every
thing that concerns himself will appear to others, makes those frivolous
calamities turn up in the same ridiculous light to him, in which he knows they
will certainly be considered by them.
I.II.34
Our sympathy, on the contrary, with deep distress, is very strong and very
sincere. It is unnecessary to give an instance. We weep even at the feigned
representation of a tragedy. If you labour, therefore, under any signal
calamity, if by some extraordinary misfortune you are fallen into poverty, into
diseases, into disgrace and disappointment; even though your own fault may have
been, in part, the occasion, yet you may generally depend upon the sincerest
sympathy of all your friends, and, as far as interest and honour will permit,
upon their kindest assistance too. But if your misfortune is not of this
dreadful kind, if you have only been a little baulked in your ambition, if you
have only been jilted by your mistress, or are only hen-pecked by your wife,
lay your account with the raillery of all your acquaintance.
I.II.35
Section III Of the Effects of
Prosperity and Adversity upon the Judgment of Mankind with regard to the
Propriety of Action; and why it is more easy to obtain their Approbation in the
one state than in the other
Chap. I That though our sympathy with sorrow is
generally a more lively sensation than our sympathy with joy, it commonly falls
much more short of the violence of what is naturally felt by the person
principally concerned
ur sympathy with sorrow, though not more real, has been more taken notice of
than our sympathy with joy. The word sympathy, in its most proper and primitive
signification, denotes our fellow-feeling with the sufferings, not that with
the enjoyments, of others. A late ingenious and subtile philosopher thought it
necessary to prove, by arguments, that we had a real sympathy with joy, and
that congratulation was a principle of human nature. Nobody, I believe, ever
thought it necessary to prove that compassion was such.
I.III.1
First of all, our sympathy with sorrow is, in some sense, more universal than
that with joy. Though sorrow is excessive, we may still have some
fellow-feeling with it. What we feel does not, indeed, in this case, amount to
that complete sympathy, to that perfect harmony and correspondence of
sentiments which constitutes approbation. We do not weep, and exclaim, and
lament, with the sufferer. We are sensible, on the contrary, of his weak ness
and of the extravagance of his passion, and yet often feel a very sensible
concern upon his account. But if we do not entirely enter into, and go along
with, the joy of another, we have no sort of regard or fellow-feeling for it.
The man who skips and dances about with that intemperate and senseless joy
which we cannot accompany him in, is the object of our contempt and
indignation.
I.III.2
Pain besides, whether of mind or body, is a more pungent sensation than
pleasure, and our sympathy with pain, though it falls greatly short of what is
naturally felt by the sufferer, is generally a more lively and distinct
perception than our sympathy with pleasure, though this last often approaches
more nearly, as I shall shew immediately, to the natural vivacity of the
original passion.
I.III.3
Over and above all this, we often struggle to keep down our sympathy with the
sorrow of others. Whenever we are not under the observation of the sufferer, we
endeavour, for our own sake, to suppress it as much as we can, and we are not
always successful. The opposition which we make to it, and the reluctance with
which we yield to it, necessarily oblige us to take more particular notice of
it. But we never have occasion to make this opposition to our sympathy with
joy. If there is any envy in the case, we never feel the least propensity
towards it; and if there is none, we give way to it without any reluctance.*1
On the contrary, as we are always ashamed of our own envy, we often pretend,
and sometimes really wish to sympathize with the joy of others, when by that
disagreeable sentiment we are disqualified from doing so. We are glad, we say
on account of our neighbour's good fortune, when in our hearts, perhaps, we are
really sorry. We often feel a sympathy with sorrow when we would wish to be rid
of it; and we often miss that with joy when we would be glad to have it. The
obvious observation, therefore, which it naturally falls in our way to make,
is, that our propensity to sympathize with sorrow must be very strong, and our
inclination to sympathize with joy very weak.
I.III.4
Notwithstanding this prejudice, however, I will venture to affirm, that, when
there is no envy in the case, our propensity to sympathize with joy is much
stronger than our propensity to sympathize with sorrow; and that our
fellow-feeling for the agreeable emotion approaches much more nearly to the
vivacity of what is naturally felt by the persons principally concerned, than
that which we conceive for the painful one.
I.III.5
We have some indulgence for that excessive grief which we cannot entirely go
along with. We know what a prodigious effort is requisite before the sufferer
can bring down his emotions. to complete harmony and concord with those of the
spectator. Though he fails, therefore, we easily pardon him. But we have no
such indulgence for the intemperance of joy; because we are not conscious that
any such vast effort is requisite to bring it down to what we can entirely
enter into. The man who, under the greatest calamities, can command his sorrow,
seems worthy of the highest admiration; but he who, in the fulness of prosperity,
can in the same manner master his joy, seems hardly to deserve any praise. We
are sensible that there is a much wider interval in the one case than in the
other, between what is naturally felt by the person principally concerned, and
what the spectator can entirely go along with.
I.III.6
What can he added to the happiness of the man who is in health, who is out of
debt, and has a clear conscience? To one in this situation, all accessions of
fortune may properly be said to be superfluous; and if he is much elevated upon
account of them, it must be the effect of the most frivolous levity. This
situation, however, may very well be called the natural and ordinary state of
mankind. Notwithstanding the present misery and depravity of the world, so justly
lamented, this really is the state of the greater part of men. The greater part
of men, therefore, cannot find any great difficulty in elevating themselves to
all the joy which any accession to this situation can well excite in their
companion.
I.III.7
But though little can be added to this state, much may be taken from it. Though
between this condition and the highest pitch of human prosperity, the interval
is but a trifle; between it and the lowest depth of misery the distance is
immense and prodigious. Adversity, on this account, necessarily depresses the
mind of the sufferer much more below its natural state, than prosperity can
elevate him above it. The spectator therefore, must find it much more difficult
to sympathize entirely, and keep perfect time, with his sorrow, than thoroughly
to enter into his joy, and must depart much further from his own natural and
ordinary temper of mind in the one case than in the other. It is on this
account, that though our sympathy with sorrow is often a more pungent sensation
than our sympathy with joy, it always falls much more short of the violence of
what is naturally felt by the person principally concerned.
I.III.8
It is agreeable to sympathize with, joy; and wherever envy does not oppose it,
our heart abandons itself with satisfaction to the highest transports of that
delightful sentiment. But it is painful to go along with grief, and we always
enter into it with reluctance.(*) When we attend to the representation of a
tragedy, we struggle against that sympathetic sorrow which the entertainment
inspires as long as we can, and we give way to it at last only when we can no
longer avoid it: we even then endeavour to cover our concern from the company.
If we shed any tears, we carefully conceal them, and are afraid, lest the
spectators, not entering into this excessive tenderness, should regard it as
effeminacy and weakness. The wretch whose misfortunes call upon our compassion
feels with what reluctance we are likely to enter into his sorrow, and
therefore proposes his grief to us with fear and hesitation: he even smothers
the half of it, and is ashamed, upon account of this hard-heartedness of
mankind, to give vent to the fulness of his affliction. It is otherwise with
the man who riots in joy and success. Wherever envy does not interest us
against him, he expects our completest sympathy. He does not fear, therefore,
to announce himself with shouts of exultation, in full confidence that we are
heartily disposed to go along with him.
I.III.9
Why should we be more ashamed to weep than to laugh before company? We may
often have as real occasion to do the one as to do the other. but we always
feel that the spectators are more likely to go along with us in the agreeable,
than in the painful emotion. It is always miserable to complain, even when we
are oppressed by the most dreadful calamities. But the triumph of victory is
not always ungraceful. Prudence, indeed, would often advise us to bear our
prosperity with more moderation; because prudence would teach us to avoid that
envy which this very triumph is, more than any thing, apt to excite.
I.III.10
How hearty are the acclamations of the mob, who never bear any envy to their
superiors, at a triumph or a public entry? And how sedate and moderate is
commonly their grief at an execution? Our sorrow at a funeral generally amounts
to no more than an affected gravity. but our mirth at a christening or a
marriage, is always from the heart, and without any affectation. Upon these,
and all such joyous occasions, our satisfaction, though not so durable, is
often as lively as that of the persons principally concerned. Whenever we
cordially congratulate our friends, which, however, to the disgrace of human
nature, we do but seldom, their joy literally becomes our joy. we are, for the
moment, as happy as they are: our heart swells and overflows with real
pleasure: joy and complacency sparkle from our eyes, and animate every feature
of our countenance, and every gesture of our body.
I.III.11
But, on the contrary, when we condole with our friends in their afflictions,
how little do we feel, in comparison of what they feel? We sit down by them, we
look at them, and while they relate to us the circumstances of their
misfortune, we listen to them with gravity and attention. But while their
narration is every moment interrupted by those natural bursts of passion which
often seem almost to choak them in the midst of it; how far are the languid
emotions of our hearts from keeping time to the transports of theirs? We may be
sensible, at the same time, that their passion is natural, and no greater than
what we ourselves might feel upon the like occasion. We may even inwardly
reproach ourselves with our own want of sensibility, and perhaps, on that
account, work ourselves up into an artificial sympathy, which, however, when it
is raised, is always the slightest and most transitory imaginable; and
generally, as soon as we have left the room, vanishes, and is gone for ever.
Nature, it seems, when she loaded us with our own sorrows, thought that they
were enough, and therefore did not command us to take any further share in
those of others, than what was necessary to prompt us to relieve them.
I.III.12
It is on account of this dull sensibility to the afflictions of others, that
magnanimity amidst great distress appears always so divinely graceful. His
behaviour is genteel and agreeable who can maintain his cheerfulness amidst a
number of frivolous disasters. But he appears to be more than mortal who can
support in the same manner the most dreadful calamities. We feel what an
immense effort is requisite to silence those violent emotions which naturally
agitate and distract those in his situation. We are amazed to find that he can
command himself so entirely. His firmness, at the same time, perfectly
coincides with our insensibility. He makes no demand upon us for that more
exquisite degree of sensibility which we find, and which we are mortified to
find, that we do not possess. There is the most perfect correspondence between
his sentiments and ours, and on that account the most perfect propriety in his
behaviour. It is a propriety too, which, from our experience of the usual
weakness of human nature, we could not reasonably have expected he should be
able to maintain. We wonder with surprise and astonishment at that strength of
mind which is capable of so noble and generous an effort. The sentiment of
complete sympathy and approbation, mixed and animated with wonder and surprise,
constitutes what is properly called admiration, as has already been more than
once taken notice of Cato, surrounded on all sides by his enemies, unable to
resist them, disdaining to submit to them, and reduced, by the proud maxims of
that age, to the necessity of destroying himself; yet never shrinking from his
misfortunes, never supplicating with the lamentable voice of wretchedness,
those miserable sympathetic tears which we are always so unwilling to give; but
on the contrary, arming himself with manly fortitude, and the moment before he
executes his fatal resolution, giving, with his usual tranquillity, all
necessary orders for the safety of his friends; appears to Seneca, that great
preacher of insensibility, a spectacle which even the gods themselves might
behold with pleasure and admiration.
I.III.13
Whenever we meet, in common life, with any examples of such heroic magnanimity,
we are always extremely affected. We are more apt to weep and shed tears for
such as, in this manner, seem to feel nothing for them. and in selves, than for
those who give way to all the weakness of sorrow: this particular case, the
sympathetic grief of the spectator appears to go beyond the original passion in
the person principally concerned. The friends of Socrates all wept when he
drank the last potion, while he himself expressed the gayest and most cheerful
tranquillity. Upon all such occasions the spectator makes no effort, and has no
occasion to make any, in order to conquer his sympathetic sorrow. He is under
no fear that it will transport him to any thing that is extravagant and
improper; he is rather pleased with the sensibility of his own heart, and gives
way to it with complacence and self-approbation. He gladly indulges, therefore,
the most melancholy views which can naturally occur to him, concerning the
calamity of his friend, for whom, perhaps, he never felt so exquisitely before,
the tender and tearful passion of love. But it is quite otherwise with the
person principally concerned. He is obliged, as much as possible, to turn away
his eyes from whatever is either naturally terrible or disagreeable in his
situation. Too serious an attention to those circumstances, he fears, might
make so violent an impression upon him, that he could no longer keep within the
bounds of moderation, or render himself the object of the complete sympathy and
approbation of the spectators. He fixes his thoughts, therefore, upon those
only which are agreeable, the applause and admiration which he is about to
deserve by the heroic magnanimity of his behaviour. To feel that he is capable
of so noble and generous an effort, to feel that in this dreadful situation he
can still act as he would desire to act, animates and transports him with joy,
and enables him to support that triumphant gaiety which seems to exult in the
victory he thus gains over his misfortunes.
I.III.14
On the contrary, he always appears, in some measure, mean and despicable, who
is sunk in sorrow and dejection upon account of any calamity of his own. We
cannot bring ourselves to feel for him what he feels for himself, and what,
perhaps, we should feel for ourselves if in his situation: we, therefore,
despise him; unjustly, perhaps, if any sentiment could be regarded as unjust,
to which we are by nature irresistibly determined. The weakness of sorrow never
appears in any respect agreeable, except when it arises from what we feel for
others more than from what we feel for ourselves. A son, upon the death of an
indulgent and respectable father, may give way to it without much blame. His
sorrow is chiefly founded upon a sort of sympathy with his departed parent and
we readily enter into this humane emotion. But if he should indulge the same
weakness upon account of any misfortune which affected himself only, he would
no longer meet with any such indulgence. If he should be reduced to beggary and
ruin, if he should be exposed to the most dreadful dangers, if he should even
be led out to a public execution, and there shed one single tear upon the
scaffold, he would disgrace himself for ever in the opinion of all the gallant
and generous part of mankind. Their compassion for him, however, would be very
strong, and very sincere; but as it would still fall short of this excessive
weakness, they would have no pardon for the man who could thus expose himself
in the eyes of the world. His behaviour would affect them with shame rather
than with sorrow; and the dishonour which he had thus brought upon himself
would appear to them the most lamentable circumstance in his misfortune. How
did it disgrace the memory of the intrepid Duke of Biron, who had so often
braved death in the field, that he wept upon the scaffold, when he beheld the
state to which he was fallen, and remembered the favour and the glory from
which his own rashness had so unfortunately thrown him!
I.III.15
Chap. II Of the origin of
Ambition, and of the distinction of Ranks
It is because mankind are disposed to sympathize more entirely with our joy
than with our sorrow, that we make parade of our riches, and conceal our
poverty. Nothing is so mortifying as to be obliged to expose our distress to
the view of the public, and to feel, that though our situation is open to the
eyes of all mankind, no mortal conceives for us the half of what we suffer.
Nay, it is chiefly from this regard to the sentiments of mankind, that we
pursue riches and avoid poverty. For to what purpose is all the toil and bustle
of this world? what is the end of avarice and ambition, of the pursuit of
wealth, of power, and preheminence? Is it to supply the necessities of nature?
The wages of the meanest labourer can supply them. We see that they afford him
food and clothing, the comfort of a house, and of a family. If we examined his
oeconomy with rigour, we should find that he spends a great part of them upon
conveniencies, which may be regarded as superfluities, and that, upon
extraordinary occasions, he can give something even to vanity and distinction.
What then is the cause of our aversion to his situation, and why should those
who have been educated in the higher ranks of life, regard it as worse than
death, to be reduced to live, even without labour, upon the same simple fare
with him, to dwell under the same lowly roof, and to be clothed in the same
humble. attire? Do they imagine that their stomach is better, or their sleep
sounder in a palace than in a cottage? The contrary has been so often observed,
and, indeed, is so very obvious, though it had never been observed, that there
is nobody ignorant of it. From whence, then, arises that emulation which runs
through all the different ranks of men, and what are the advantages which we
propose by that great purpose of human life which we call bettering our
condition? To be observed, to be attended to, to be taken notice of with
sympathy, complacency, and approbation, are all the advantages which we can
propose to derive from it. It is the vanity, not the ease, or the pleasure,
which interests us. But vanity is always founded upon the belief of our being
the object of attention and approbation. The rich man glories in his riches,
because he feels that they naturally draw upon him the attention of the world,
and that mankind are disposed to go along with him in all those agreeable
emotions with which the advantages of his situation so readily inspire him. At
the thought of this, his heart seems to swell and dilate itself within him, and
he is fonder of his wealth, upon this account, than for all the other
advantages it procures him. The poor man, on the contrary, is ashamed of his
poverty. He feels that it either places him out of the sight of mankind, or,
that if they take any notice of him, they have, however, scarce any
fellow-feeling with the misery and distress which he suffers. He is mortified
upon both accounts. for though to be overlooked, and to be disapproved of, are
things entirely different, yet as obscurity covers us from the daylight of
honour and approbation, to feel that we are taken no notice of, necessarily
damps the most agreeable hope, and disappoints the most ardent desire, of human
nature. The poor man goes out and comes in unheeded, and when in the midst of a
crowd is in the same obscurity as if shut up in his own hovel. Those humble
cares and painful attentions which occupy those in his situation, afford no
amusement to the dissipated and the gay. They turn away their eyes from him, or
if the extremity of his distress forces them to look at him, it is only to
spurn so disagreeable an object from among them. The fortunate and the proud
wonder at the insolence of human wretchedness, that it should dare to present
itself before them, and with the loathsome aspect of its misery presume to
disturb the serenity of their happiness. The man of rank and distinction, on
the contrary, is observed by all the world. Every body is eager to look at him,
and to conceive, at least by sympathy, that joy and exultation with which his
circumstances naturally inspire him. His actions are the objects of the public
care. Scarce a word, scarce a gesture, can fall from him that is altogether
neglected. In a great assembly he is the person upon whom all direct their
eyes; it is upon him that their passions seem all to wait with expectation, in
order to receive that movement and direction which he shall impress upon them;
and if his behaviour is not altogether absurd, he has, every moment, an
opportunity of interesting mankind, and of rendering himself the object of the
observation and fellow-feeling of every body about him. It is this, which,
notwithstanding the restraint it imposes, notwithstanding the loss of liberty
with which it is attended, renders greatness the object of envy, and
compensates, in the opinion of all those mortifications which must mankind, all
that toil, all that anxiety, be undergone in the pursuit of it; and what is of
yet more consequence, all that leisure, all that ease, all that careless security,
which are forfeited for ever by the acquisition.
I.III.16
When we consider the condition of the great, in those delusive colours in which
the imagination is apt to paint it. it seems to be almost the abstract idea of
a perfect and happy state. It is the very state which, in all our waking dreams
and idle reveries, we had sketched out to ourselves as the final object of all
our desires. We feel, therefore, a peculiar sympathy with the satisfaction of
those who are in it. We favour all their inclinations, and forward all their
wishes. What pity, we think, that any thing should spoil and corrupt so
agreeable a situation! We could even wish them immortal; and it seems hard to
us, that death should at last put an end to such perfect enjoyment. It is cruel,
we think, in Nature to compel them from their exalted stations to that humble,
but hospitable home, which she has provided for all her children. Great King,
live for ever! is the compliment, which, after the manner of eastern adulation,
we should readily make them, if experience did not teach us its absurdity.
Every calamity that befals them, every injury that is done them, excites in the
breast of the spectator ten times more compassion and resentment than he would
have felt, had the same things happened to other men. It is the misfortunes of
Kings only which afford the proper subjects for tragedy. They resemble, in this
respect, the misfortunes of lovers. Those two situations are the chief which
interest us upon the theatre; because, in spite of all that reason and
experience can tell us to the contrary, the prejudices of the imagination
attach to these two states a happiness superior to any other. To disturb, or to
put an end to such perfect enjoyment, seems to be the most atrocious of all
injuries. The traitor who conspires against the life of his monarch, is thought
a greater monster than any other murderer. All the innocent blood that was shed
in the civil wars, provoked less indignation than the death of Charles I. A
stranger to human nature, who saw the indifference of men about the misery of
their inferiors, and the regret and indignation which they feel for the
misfortunes and sufferings of those above them, would be apt to imagine, that
pain must be more agonizing, and the convulsions of death more terrible to
persons of higher rank, than to those of meaner stations.
I.III.17
Upon this disposition of mankind, to go along with all the passions of the rich
and the powerful, is founded the distinction of ranks, and the order of
society. Our obsequiousness to our superiors more frequently arises from our
admiration for the advantages of their situation, than from any private
expectations of benefit from their good-will. Their benefits can extend but to
a few. but their fortunes interest almost every body. We are eager to assist
them in completing a system of happiness that approaches so near to perfection;
and we desire to serve them for their own sake, without any other recompense
but the vanity or the honour of obliging them. Neither is our deference to
their inclinations founded chiefly, or altogether, upon a regard to the utility
of such submission, and to the order of society, which is best supported by it.
Even when the order of society seems to require that we should oppose them, we
can hardly bring ourselves to do it. That kings are the servants of the people,
to be obeyed, resisted, deposed, or punished, as the public conveniency may
require, is the doctrine of reason and philosophy; but it is not the doctrine
of Nature. Nature would teach us to submit to them for their own sake, to
tremble and bow down before their exalted station, to regard their smile as a
reward sufficient to compensate any services, and to dread their displeasure,
though no other evil were to follow from it, as the severest of all
mortifications. To treat them in any respect as men, to reason and dispute with
them upon ordinary occasions, requires such resolution, that there are few men
whose magnanimity can support them in it, unless they are likewise assisted by
familiarity and acquaintance. The strongest motives, the most furious passions,
fear, hatred, and resentment, are scarce sufficient to balance this natural
disposition to respect them: and their conduct must, either justly or unjustly,
have excited the highest degree of all those passions, before the bulk of the
people can be brought to oppose them with violence, or to desire to see them
either punished or deposed. Even when the people have been brought this length,
they are apt to relent every moment, and easily relapse into their habitual
state of deference to those whom they have been accustomed to look upon as
their natural superiors. They cannot stand the mortification of their monarch.
Compassion soon takes the place of resentment, they forget all past provocations,
their old principles of loyalty revive, and they run to re-establish the ruined
authority of their old masters, with the same violence with which they had
opposed it. The death of Charles I. brought about the Restoration of the royal
family. Compassion for James II. when he was seized by the populace in making
his escape on ship-board, had almost prevented the Revolution, and made it go
on more heavily than before.
I.III.18
Do the great seem insensible of the easy price at which they may acquire the
public admiration; or do they seem to imagine that to them, as to other men, it
must be the purchase either of sweat or of blood? By what important
accomplishments is the young nobleman instructed to support the dignity of his
rank, and to render himself worthy of that superiority over his
fellow-citizens, to which the virtue of his ancestors had raised them? Is it by
knowledge, by industry, by patience, by self-denial, or by virtue of any kind?
As all his words, as all his motions are attended to, he learns an habitual
regard to every circumstance of ordinary behaviour, and studies to perform all
those small duties with the most exact propriety. As he is conscious how much
he is observed, and how much mankind are disposed to favour all his inclinations,
he acts, upon the most indifferent occasions, with that freedom and elevation
which the thought of this naturally inspires. His air, his manner, his
deportment, all mark that elegant and graceful sense of his own superiority,
which those who are born to inferior stations can hardly ever arrive at. These
are the arts by which he proposes to make mankind more easily submit to his
authority, and to govern their inclinations according to his own pleasure: and
in this he is seldom disappointed. These arts, supported by rank and
preheminence, are, upon ordinary occasions, sufficient to govern the world.
Lewis XIV. during the greater part of his reign, was regarded, not only in
France, but over all Europe, as the most perfect model of a great prince. But
what were the talents and virtues by which he acquired this great reputation?
Was it by the scrupulous and inflexible justice of all his undertakings, by the
immense dangers and difficulties with which they were attended, or by the
unwearied and unrelenting application with which he pursued them? Was it by his
extensive knowledge, by his exquisite judgment, or by his heroic valour? It was
by none of these qualities. But he was, first of all, the most powerful prince
in Europe, and consequently held the highest rank among kings; and then, says
his historian, 'he surpassed all his courtiers in the gracefulness of his
shape, and the majestic beauty of his features. The sound of his voice, noble
and affecting, gained those hearts which his presence intimidated. He had a
step and a deportment which could suit only him and his rank, and which would
have been ridiculous in any other person. The embarrassment which he occasioned
to those who spoke to him, flattered that secret satisfaction with which he
felt his own superiority. The old officer, who was confounded and faultered in
asking him a favour, and not being able to conclude his discourse, said to him:
Sir, your majesty, I hope, will believe that I do not tremble thus before your
enemies: had no difficulty to obtain what he demanded.' These frivolous
accomplishments, supported by his rank, and, no doubt too, by a degree of other
talents and virtues, which seems, however, not to have been much above
mediocrity, established this prince in the esteem of his own age, and have
drawn, even from posterity, a good deal of respect for his memory. Compared
with these, in his own times, and in his own presence, no other virtue, it
seems, appeared to have any merit. Knowledge, industry, valour, and
beneficence, trembled, were abashed, and lost all dignity before them.
I.III.19
But it is not by accomplishments of this kind, that the man of inferior rank
must hope to distinguish himself. Politeness is so much the virtue of the
great, that it will do little honour to any body but themselves. The coxcomb,
who imitates their manner, and affects to be eminent by the superior propriety
of his ordinary behaviour, is rewarded with a double share of contempt for his
folly and presumption. Why should the man, whom nobody thinks it worth while to
look at, be very anxious about the manner in which he holds up his head, or
disposes of his arms while he walks through a room? He is occupied surely with
a very superfluous attention, and with an attention too that marks a sense of
his own importance, which no other mortal can go along with. The most perfect
modesty and plainness, joined to as much negligence as is consistent with the
respect due to the company, ought to be the chief characteristics of the
behaviour of a private man. If ever he hopes to distinguish himself, it must be
by more important virtues. He must acquire dependants to balance the dependants
of the great, and he has no other fund to pay them from, but the labour of his
body, and the activity of his mind. He must cultivate these therefore: he must
acquire superior knowledge in his profession, and superior industry in the
exercise of it. He must be patient in labour, resolute in danger, and firm in
distress. These talents he must bring into public view, by the difficulty, importance,
and, at the same time, good judgment of his undertakings, and by the severe and
unrelenting application with which he pursues them. Probity and prudence,
generosity and frankness, must characterize his behaviour upon all ordinary
occasions; and he must, at the same time, be forward to engage in all those
situations, in which it requires the greatest talents and virtues to act with
propriety, but in which the greatest applause is to be acquired by those who
can acquit themselves with honour. With what impatience does the man of spirit
and ambition, who is depressed by his situation, look round for some great
opportunity to distinguish himself? No circumstances, which can afford this,
appear to him undesirable. He even looks forward with satisfaction to the
prospect of foreign war, or civil dissension; and, with secret transport and
delight, sees through all the confusion and bloodshed which attend them, the
probability of those wished-for occasions presenting themselves, in which he
may draw upon himself the attention and admiration of mankind. The man of rank
and distinction, on the contrary, whose whole glory consists in the propriety
of his ordinary behaviour, who is contented with the humble renown which this
can afford him, and has no talents to acquire any other, is unwilling to
embarrass himself with what can be attended either with difficulty or distress.
To figure at a ball is his great triumph, and to succeed in an intrigue of
gallantry, his highest exploit. He has an aversion to all public confusions,
not from the love of mankind, for the great never look upon their inferiors as
their fellow-creatures; nor yet from want of courage, for in that he is seldom
defective; but from a consciousness that he possesses none of the virtues which
are required in such situations, and that the public attention will certainly
be drawn away from him by others. He may be willing to expose himself to some
little danger, and to make a campaign when it happens to be the fashion. But he
shudders with horror at the thought of any situation which demands the
continual and long exertion of patience, industry, fortitude, and application
of thought. These virtues are hardly ever to be met with in men who are born to
those high stations. In all governments accordingly, even in monarchies, the
highest offices are generally possessed, and the whole detail of the
administration conducted, by men who were educated in the middle and inferior
ranks of life, who have been carried forward by their own industry and
abilities, though loaded with the jealousy, and opposed by the resentment, of
all those who were born their superiors, and to whom the great, after having
regarded them first with contempt, and afterwards with envy, are at last
contented to truckle with the same abject meanness with which they desire that
the rest of mankind should behave to themselves.
I.III.20
It is the loss of this easy empire over the affections of mankind which renders
the fall from greatness so insupportable. When the family of the king of
Macedon was led in triumph by Paulus Aemilius, their misfortunes, it is said,
made them divide with their conqueror the attention of the Roman people. The
sight of the royal children, whose tender age rendered them insensible of their
situation, struck the spectators, amidst the public rejoicings and prosperity,
with the tenderest sorrow and compassion. The king appeared next in the
procession; and seemed like one confounded and astonished, and bereft of all
sentiment, by the greatness of his calamities. His friends and ministers
followed after him. As they moved along, they often cast their eyes upon their
fallen sovereign, and always burst into tears at the sight; their whole
behaviour demonstrating that they thought not of their own misfortunes, but
were occupied entirely by the superior greatness of his. The generous Romans,
on the contrary, beheld him with disdain and indignation, and regarded as
unworthy of all compassion the man who could be so mean-spirited as to bear to
live under such calamities. Yet what did those calamities amount to? According
to the greater part of historians, he was to spend the remainder of his days,
under the protection of a powerful and humane people, in a state which in
itself should seem worthy of envy, a state of plenty, ease, leisure, and
security, from which it was impossible for him even by his own folly to fall.
But he was no longer to be surrounded by that admiring mob of fools,
flatterers, and dependants, who had formerly been accustomed to attend upon all
his motions. He was no longer to be gazed upon by multitudes, nor to have it in
his power to render himself the object of their respect, their gratitude, their
love, their admiration. The passions of nations were no longer to mould
themselves upon his inclinations. This was that insupportable calamity which
bereaved the king of all sentiment; which made his friends forget their own
misfortunes; and which the Roman magnanimity could scarce conceive how any man
could be so mean-spirited as to bear to survive.
I.III.21
'Love,' says my Lord Rochfaucault, 'is commonly succeeded by ambition; but
ambition is hardly ever succeeded by love.' That passion, when once it has got
entire possession of the breast, will admit neither a rival nor a successor. To
those who have been accustomed to the possession, or even to the hope of public
admiration, all other pleasures sicken and decay. Of all the discarded
statesmen who for their own ease have studied to get the better of ambition,
and to despise those honours which they could no longer arrive at, how few have
been able to succeed? The greater part have spent their time in the most
listless and insipid indolence, chagrined at the thoughts of their own
insignificancy, incapable of being interested i n the occupations of private
life, without enjoyment, except when they talked of their former greatness, and
without satisfaction, except when they were employed in some vain project to
recover it. Are you in earnest resolved never to barter your liberty for the
lordly servitude of a court, but to live free, fearless, and independent? There
seems to be one way to continue in that virtuous resolution; and perhaps but
one. Never enter the place from whence so few have been able to return; never
come within the circle of ambition; nor ever bring yourself into comparison
with those masters of the earth who have already engrossed the attention of
half mankind before you.
I.III.22
Of such mighty importance does it appear to be, in the imaginations of men, to
stand in that situation which sets them most in the view of general sympathy
and attention. And thus, place, that great object which divides the wives of
aldermen, is the end of half the labours of human life; and is the cause of all
the tumult and bustle, all the rapine and injustice, which avarice and ambition
have introduced into this world. People of sense, it is said, indeed despise
place; that is, they despise sitting at the head of the table, and are
indifferent who it is that is pointed out to the company by that frivolous
circumstance, which the smallest advantage is capable of overbalancing. But
rank, distinction pre-eminence, no man despises, unless he is either raised
very much above, or sunk very much below, the ordinary standard of human
nature; unless he is either so confirmed in wisdom and real philosophy, as to
be satisfied that, while the propriety of his conduct renders him the just
object of approbation, it is of little consequence though he be neither
attended to, nor approved of; or so habituated to the idea of his own meanness,
so sunk in slothful and sottish indifference, as entirely to have forgot the
desire, and almost the very wish, for superiority.
I.III.23
As to become the natural object of the joyous congratulations and sympathetic
attentions of mankind is, in this manner, the circumstance which gives to
prosperity all its dazzling splendour; so nothing darkens so much the gloom of
adversity as to feel that our misfortunes are the objects, not of the
fellow-feeling, but of the contempt and aversion of our brethren. It is upon
this account that the most dreadful calamities are not always those which it is
most difficult to support. It is often more mortifying to appear in public
under small disasters, than under great misfortunes. The first excite no
sympathy; but the second, though they may excite none that approaches to the
anguish of the sufferer, call forth, however, a very lively compassion. The
sentiments of the spectators are, in this last case, less wide of those of the
sufferer, and their imperfect fellow-feeling lends him some assistance in
supporting his misery. Before a gay assembly, a gentleman would be more
mortified to appear covered with filth and rags than with blood and wounds.
This last situation would interest their pity; the other would provoke their
laughter. The judge who orders a criminal to be set in the pillory, dishonours
him more than if he had condemned him to the scaffold. The great prince, who,
some years ago, caned a general officer at the head of his army, disgraced him
irrecoverably. The punishment would have been much less had he shot him through
the body. By the laws of honour, to strike with a cane dishonours, to strike
with a sword does not, for an obvious reason. Those slighter punishments, when
inflicted on a gentleman, to whom dishonour is the greatest of all evils, come
to be regarded among a humane and generous people, as the most dreadful of any.
With regard to persons of that rank, therefore, they are universally laid
aside, and the law, while it takes their life upon many occasions, respects
their honour upon almost all. To scourge a person of quality, or to set him in
the pillory, upon account of any crime whatever, is a brutality of which no
European government, except that of Russia, is capable.
I.III.24
A brave man is not rendered contemptible by being brought to the scaffold; he
is, by being set in the pillory. His behaviour in the one situation may gain
him universal esteem and admiration. No behaviour in the other can render him
agreeable. The sympathy of the spectators supports him in the one case, and
saves him from that shame, that consciousness that his misery is felt by
himself only, which is of all sentiments the most unsupportable. There is no
sympathy in the other; or, if there is any, it is not with his pain, which is a
trifle, but with his consciousness of the want of sympathy with which this pain
is attended. It is with his shame, not with his sorrow. Those who pity him,
blush and hang down their heads for him. He droops in the same manner, and
feels himself irrecoverably degraded by the punishment, though not by the
crime. The man, on the contrary, who dies with resolution, as he is naturally
regarded with the erect aspect of esteem and approbation, so he wears himself
the same undaunted countenance; and, if the crime does not deprive him of the
respect of others, the punishment never will. He has no suspicion that his
situation is the object of contempt or derision to any body, and he can, with
propriety, assume the air, not only of perfect serenity, but of triumph and
exultation.
I.III.25
'Great dangers,' says the Cardinal de Retz, 'have their charms, because there
is some glory to be got, even when we miscarry. But moderate dangers have
nothing but what is horrible, because the loss of reputation always attends the
want of success.' His maxim has the same foundation with what we have been just
now observing with regard to punishments.
I.III.26
Human virtue is superior to pain, to poverty, to danger, and to death; nor does
it even require its utmost efforts do despise them. But to have its misery
exposed to insult and derision, to be led in triumph, to be set up for the hand
of scorn to point at, is a situation in which its constancy is much more apt to
fail. Compared with the contempt of mankind, all other external evils are
easily supported.
I.III.27
Chap. III Of the corruption of
our moral sentiments, which is occasioned by this disposition to admire the
rich and the great, and to despise or neglect persons of poor and mean
condition
This disposition to admire, and almost to worship, the rich and the powerful,
and to despise, or, at least, to neglect persons of poor and mean condition,
though necessary both to establish and to maintain the distinction of ranks and
the order of society, is, at the same time, the great and most universal cause
of the corruption of our moral sentiments. That wealth and greatness are often
regarded with the respect and admiration which are due only to wisdom and
virtue; and that the contempt, of which vice and folly are the only proper
objects, is often most unjustly bestowed upon poverty and weakness, has been
the complaint of moralists in all ages.
I.III.28
We desire both to be respectable and to be respected. We dread both to be
contemptible and to be contemned. But, upon coming into the world, we soon find
that wisdom and virtue are by no means the sole objects of respect; nor vice
and folly, of contempt. We frequently see the respectful attentions of the
world more strongly directed towards the rich and the great, than towards the
wise and the virtuous. We see frequently the vices and follies of the powerful
much less despised than the poverty and weakness of the innocent. To deserve,
to acquire, and to enjoy the respect and admiration of mankind, are the great
objects of ambition and emulation. Two different roads are presented to us,
equally leading to the attainment of this so much desired object; the one, by
the study of wisdom and the practice of virtue; the other, by the acquisition
of wealth and greatness. Two different characters are presented to our
emulation; the one, of proud ambition and ostentatious avidity. the other, of
humble modesty and equitable justice. Two different models, two different
pictures, are held out to us, according to which we may fashion our own
character and behaviour; the one more gaudy and glittering in its colouring;
the other more correct and more exquisitely beautiful in its outline: the one
forcing itself upon the notice of every wandering eye; the other, attracting
the attention of scarce any body but the most studious and careful observer.
They are the wise and the virtuous chiefly, a select, though, I am afraid, but
a small party, who are the real and steady admirers of wisdom and virtue. The
great mob of mankind are the admirers and worshippers, and, what may seem more
extraordinary, most frequently the disinterested admirers and worshippers, of
wealth and greatness.
I.III.29
The respect which we feel for wisdom and virtue is, no doubt, different from
that which we conceive for wealth and greatness; and it requires no very nice
discernment to distinguish the difference. But, notwithstanding this
difference, those sentiments bear a very considerable resemblance to one
another. In some particular features they are, no doubt, different, but, in the
general air of the countenance, they seem to be so very nearly the same, that
inattentive observers are very apt to mistake the one for the other.
I.III.30
In equal degrees of merit there is scarce any man who does not respect more the
rich and the great, than the poor and the humble. With most men the presumption
and vanity of the former are much more admired, than the real and solid merit
of the latter. It is scarce agreeable to good morals, or even to good language,
perhaps, to say, that mere wealth and greatness, abstracted from merit and
virtue, deserve our respect. We must acknowledge, however, that they almost
constantly obtain it; and that they may, therefore, be considered as, in some
respects, the natural objects of it. Those exalted stations may, no doubt, be
completely degraded by vice and folly. But the vice and folly must be very
great, before they can operate this complete degradation. The profligacy of a
man of fashion is looked upon with much less contempt and aversion, than that
of a man of meaner condition. In the latter, a single transgression of the
rules of temperance and propriety, is commonly more resented, than the constant
and avowed contempt of them ever is in the former.
I.III.31
In the middling and inferior stations of life, the road to virtue and that to
fortune, to such fortune, at least, as men in such stations can reasonably
expect to acquire, are, happily in most cases, very nearly the same. In all the
middling and inferior professions, real and solid professional abilities,
joined to prudent, just, firm, and temperate conduct, can very seldom fail of
success. Abilities will even sometimes prevail where the conduct is by no means
correct. Either habitual imprudence, however, or injustice, or weakness, or
profligacy, will always clouD, and sometimes Depress altogether, the most
splendid professional abilities. Men in the inferior and middling stations of
life, besides, can never be great enough to be above the law, which must generally
overawe them into some sort of respect for, at least, the more important rules
of justice. The success of such people, too, almost always depends upon the
favour and good opinion of their neighbours and equals; and without a tolerably
regular conduct these can very seldom be obtained. The good old proverb,
therefore, That honesty is the best policy, holds, in such situations, almost
always perfectly true. In such situations, therefore, we may generally expect a
considerable degree of virtue; and, fortunately for the good morals of society,
these are the situations of by far the greater part of mankind.
I.III.32
In the superior stations of life the case is unhappily not always the same. In
the courts of princes, in the drawing-rooms of the great, where success and
preferment depend, not upon the esteem of intelligent and well-informed equals,
but upon the fanciful and foolish favour of ignorant, presumptuous, and proud
superiors; flattery and falsehood too often prevail over merit and abilities.
In such societies the abilities to please, are more regarded than the abilities
to serve. In quiet and peaceable times, when the storm is at a distance, the
prince, or great man, wishes only to be amused, and is even apt to fancy that
he has scarce any occasion for the service of any body, or that those who amuse
him are sufficiently able to serve him. The external graces, the frivolous
accomplishments of that impertinent and foolish thing called a man of fashion,
are commonly more admired than the solid and masculine virtues of a warrior, a
statesman, a philosopher, or a legislator. All the great and awful virtues, all
the virtues which can fit, either for the council, the senate, or the field,
are, by the insolent and insignificant flatterers, who commonly figure the most
in such corrupted societies, held in the utmost contempt and derision. When the
duke of Sully was called upon by Lewis the Thirteenth, to give his advice in
some great emergency, he observed the favourites and courtiers whispering to
one another, and smiling at his unfashionable appearance. 'Whenever your
majesty's father,' said the old warrior and statesman, 'did me the honour to
consult me, he ordered the buffoons of the court to retire into the
antechamber.'
I.III.33
It is from our disposition to admire, and consequently to imitate, the rich and
the great, that they are enabled to set, or to lead what is called the fashion.
Their dress is the fashionable dress; the language of their conversation, the
fashionable style; their air and deportment, the fashionable behaviour. Even
their vices and follies are fashionable; and the greater part of men are proud
to imitate and resemble them in the very qualities which dishonour and degrade
them. Vain men often give themselves airs of a fashionable profligacy, which,
in their hearts, they do not approve of, and of which, perhaps, they are really
not guilty. They desire to be praised for what they themselves do not think
praise-worthy, and are ashamed of unfashionable virtues which they sometimes practise
in secret, and for which they have secretly some degree of real veneration.
There are hypocrites of wealth and greatness, as well as of religion and
virtue; and a vain man is as apt to pretend to be what he is not, in the one
way, as a cunning man is in the other. He assumes the equipage and splendid way
of living of his superiors, without considering that whatever may be
praise-worthy in any of these, derives its whole merit and propriety from its
suitableness to that situation and fortune which both require and can easily
support the expence. Many a poor man places his glory in being thought rich,
without considering that the duties (if one may call such follies by so very
venerable a name) which that reputation imposes upon him, must soon reduce him to
beggary, and render his situation still more unlike that of those whom he
admires and imitates, than it had been originally.
I.III.34
To attain to this envied situation, the candidates for fortune too frequently
abandon the paths of virtue; for unhappily, the road which leads to the one,
and that which leads to the other, lie sometimes in very opposite directions.
But the ambitious man flatters himself that, in the splendid situation to which
he advances, he will have so many means of commanding the respect and
admiration of mankind, and will be enabled to act with such superior propriety
and grace, that the lustre of his future conduct will entirely cover, or
efface, the foulness of the steps by which he arrived at that elevation. In
many governments the candidates for the highest stations are above the law;
and, if they can attain the object of their ambition, they have no fear of
being called to account for the means by which they acquired it. They often
endeavour, therefore, not only by fraud and falsehood, the ordinary and vulgar
arts of intrigue and cabal; but sometimes by the perpetration of the most
enormous crimes, by murder and assassination, by rebellion and civil war, to
supplant and destroy those who oppose or stand in the way of their greatness.
They more frequently miscarry than succeed; and commonly gain nothing but the
disgraceful punishment which is due to their crimes. But, though they should be
so lucky as to attain that wished-for greatness, they are always most miserably
disappointed in the happiness which they expect to enjoy in it. It is not ease
or pleasure, but always honour, of one kind or another, though frequently an
honour very ill understood, that the ambitious man really pursues. But the
honour of his exalted station appears, both in his own eyes and in those of
other people, polluted and defiled by the baseness of the means through which
he rose to it. Though by the profusion of every liberal expence; though by
excessive indulgence in every profligate pleasure, the wretched, but usual,
resource of ruined characters; though by the hurry of public business, or by
the prouder and more dazzling tumult of war, he may endeavour to efface, both
from his own memory and from that of other people, the remembrance of what he
has done; that remembrance never fails to pursue him. He invokes in vain the
dark and dismal powers of forgetfulness and oblivion. He remembers himself what
he has done, and that remembrance tells him that other people must likewise
remember it. Amidst all the gaudy pomp of the most ostentatious greatness;
amidst the venal and vile adulation of the great and of the learned; amidst the
more innocent, though more foolish, acclamations of the common people; amidst
all the pride of conquest and the triumph of successful war, he is still
secretly pursued by the avenging furies of shame and remorse; and, while glory
seems to surround him on all sides, he himself, in his own imagination, sees
black and foul infamy fast pursuing him, and every moment ready to overtake him
from behind. Even the great Caesar, though he had the magnanimity to dismiss
his guards, could not dismiss his suspicions. The remembrance of Pharsalia
still haunted and pursued him. When, at the request of the senate, he had the
generosity to pardon Marcellus, he told that assembly, that he was not unaware
of the designs which were carrying on against his life; but that, as he had
lived long enough both for nature and for glory, he was contented to die, and
therefore despised all conspiracies. He had, perhaps, lived long enough for
nature. But the man who felt himself the object of such deadly resentment, from
those whose favour he wished to gain, and whom he still wished to consider as
his friends, had certainly lived too long for real glory; or for all the happiness
which he could ever hope to enjoy in the love and esteem of his equals.
I.III.35
______________________________________
公法评论
http://gongfa.yeah.net
http://www.gongfa.com
email to:
mountainsf@sina.com
mountainss@yahoo.com